Skip to main content
Log in

The economics of utopia: a co-evolutionary model of ideas, citizenship and socio-political change

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Journal of Evolutionary Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose a new history-friendly approach to evolutionary socio-economic dynamics based around competition between five ‘utopias’ as central ideas about which to order society: capitalism, socialism, civil liberty, nature, and nationalism. In our model, citizens contribute economic resources to support their preferred utopia, and societal dynamics are explained as a co-evolutionary process between these competing utopias. We apply the model to analyze certain aspects of socio-economic and political change in the US from the 1960s–present. We carry out a history-friendly analysis inspired by such episodes as the outbreak of civil movements in the 1970s, the rise of neo-liberalism in the 1980s, and the channels through which America has engendered an ‘age of fracture’. Further applications for empirical and theoretical research are suggested.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ideas at this scale are constitutional meso-rules (Dopfer et al. 2004; Potts 2007; Dopfer and Potts 2008).

  2. This particular set of five is somewhat arbitrary – there could be more or fewer. Our economic actor/citizen is (directly or indirectly) affected by the state of all of the subsystems but, as citizen, our agents seek to promote one of these subsystems in preference to others.

  3. In Fatas-Villafranca et al. (2011), 2009) we revise the behavioral economics and psychology literature upon which we draw to pose our changing-payoff functions, and our formal updating proposal (below).

  4. It is difficult to calibrate and measure the “level of effort” in effective terms, since it is composed of observable (time, financial and material resources) and non-observable (e.g. personal abilities, effort, skills, connections, knowledge) variables.

  5. See Hofbauer and Sigmund (1998) and Almudi et al. (2012) for analysis of coupled dynamic systems.

  6. On the key influence of Darwinian ideas in political and philosophical thought, see Dewey (1910) and Jones (1980).

  7. Although we seek to provide a stylized representation in Table 2, Page and Shapiro (1992; Ch. 3-5) present numerical info compatible with Table 2.

  8. See the initial intra-subsystem shares in Table 2 with a low value for \( {\ s}_{20}^M \); this implies that the neoliberal mass can develop in its niche with almost no direct challenge from close-moderate positions; they perceive a very low negative externality from \( {\ s}_{20}^M \).

  9. See the Mises-Keynesian debates on the viability of socialism, e.g. Paul Samuelson’s failed predictions of the future of the Soviet Union in the first edition of Economics.

  10. Note that there are a few constraints that must be taken into account when changing the values of the parameters in Table 3, namely:\( {\sum}_i{s}_{i0}^{\pi}=1 \) for all π ∈ Π, and \( {\sum}_{\pi \in \Pi}{\gamma}_0^{\pi}=1 \). To ensure that the restriction \( {\sum}_i{s}_{i0}^k=1 \) is maintained when adding a certain (positive or negative) value δ to the default value \( {\left({s}_{j0}^k\right)}^{DV} \) of any parameter \( {s}_{j0}^k \), we subtract δ/2 from the default value \( {\left({s}_{i\ne j0}^k\right)}^{DV} \) of the other two parameters \( {s}_{i\ne j0}^k \). Similarly, when adding a certain (positive or negative) value δ to the default value \( {\left({\gamma}_0^k\right)}^{DV} \) of any \( {\gamma}_0^k \), we subtract δ/4 from the default value \( {\left({\gamma}_0^{\pi \ne k}\right)}^{DV} \) of the other four parameters \( {\gamma}_0^{\pi \ne k} \) so that the restriction \( {\sum}_{\pi \in \Pi}{\gamma}_0^{\pi}=1 \) is maintained. This procedure implies that the range of admissible values that can be explored for a particular \( {s}_{j0}^k \) is often smaller than [0,1], since we must also honor the conditions \( {s}_{i\ne j0}^k\ge 0 \). To be precise, the admissible range when changing a particular \( {s}_{j0}^k \) is \( \left[0,\kern0.5em {\left({s}_{j0}^k\right)}^{DV}+2\cdotp { \min}_i{\left({s}_{i\ne j0}^k\right)}^{DV}\right] \). The same argument applies for \( {\gamma}_0^k \) and the conditions \( {\gamma}_0^{\pi \ne k}\ge 0 \). The admissible range when changing a particular \( {\gamma}_0^k \) is \( \left[0,\kern0.5em {\left({\gamma}_0^k\right)}^{DV}+4\cdotp { \min}_i{\left({\gamma}_0^{\pi \ne k}\right)}^{DV}\right] \).

  11. Only values of α and β that make 0 ≤ x i  ≤ 1 are admissible.

  12. The effect of changing the value of α is merely a change in the time scale. This can be easily proved analytically conducting a change of variable t  = α · t. The lowest value of β that we have checked is 10−5.

  13. As explained before, any change in a parameter \( {s}_{i0}^{\pi} \) or \( {\gamma}_0^{\pi} \) forces us to alter the value of other parameters to ensure that the constraints\( {\sum}_i{s}_{i0}^{\pi}=1 \) for all π ∈ Π, and \( {\sum}_{\pi \in \Pi}{\gamma}_0^{\pi}=1 \) are preserved.

  14. The population profile induced by an Evolutionary Stable Strategy is asymptotically stable in terms of the Replicator Dynamics (Hofbauer and Sigmund 1998; Weibull 1995).

  15. Note, however, that this does not imply that strategy 3 will be wiped out in the Replicator Dynamics. Weakly dominated strategies in the Replicator Dynamics may remain present forever. In this particular case, strategy 3 obtains a strictly lower payoff than strategy 1 at any point in the interior of the simplex, but the dynamics may lead the process “quickly” towards the boundary s 3 = 1 − s 1, where the selection pressure over strategy 3 disappears.

References

  • Abbot P (2005) Political thought in America. Waveland Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu D, Robinson J (2012) Why nations fail? Crown Business, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu D, Robinson J (2013) Economics versus politics: pitfalls of policy advice. J Econ Perspect 23:173–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akerlof G, Kranton R (2000) Economics and identity. Q J Econ 115(3):715–753

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Almudi I, Fatas-Villafranca F, Izquierdo LR (2012) Innovation, catch up and leadership in science-based industries. A coevolution model. Ind Corp Chang 21:345–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Almudi I, Fatas-Villafranca F, Izquierdo LR (2013) Industry dynamics, technological regimes and the role of demand. J Evol Econ 23:1073–1098

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Almudi I, Fatas-Villafranca F, Potts J (2017) Utopia competition: a new approach to the micro-foundations of sustainability transitions. J Bioecon 19:165–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson B (1983) Imaged communities: reflections on the origins and spread of nationalism. Verso, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (1996) New approaches to macroeconomic modeling. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow K (1951) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker G (1993) The economic way of looking at behavior. J Polit Econ 101:385–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beland D, Cox RH (eds) (2011) Ideas and politics in social science research. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulding K (1978) Ecodynamics. Sage Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles S, Gintis H (2011) A cooperative species. Princeton, Princeton University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan J, Tollison R (1984) The Theory of Public Choice II. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan J, Tullock G (1962) The calculus of consent. Liberty Fund Inc, Indiana

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan B (2007) The myth of the rational voter. Princeton, Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, R. (1962). Silent Spring. Houghton Mifflin

    Google Scholar 

  • Commons JR (1934) Institutional economics. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Denzau A, North D (1994) Shared mental models: ideologies and institutions. Kyklos 47(1):3–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1910) The influence of Darwin on philosophy and other essays. Henry Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Guilmi C, Landini S, Gallegati M (2017) Interactive macroeconomics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dopfer K, Potts J (2008) The general theory of economic evolution. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dopfer K, Foster J, Potts J (2004) Micro-Meso-Macro. J Evol Econ 14:263–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dosi G, Fagiolo G, Roventini A (2010) Schumpeter meeting Keynes: a policy-friendly model of endogenous growth and business cycles. J Econ Dyn Control 34(9):1748–1767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of political action in a democracy. J Polit Econ 65:135–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fatas-Villafranca F, Saura D, Vazquez FJ (2007) Emulation, prevention and social interaction in consumption dynamics. Metroeconomica 58(4):582–608

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fatas-Villafranca F, Saura D, Vazquez FJ (2009) Diversity, persistence and chaos in consumption patterns. J Bioecon 11:43–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fatas-Villafranca F, Saura D, Vazquez FJ (2011) A dynamic model of public opinion formation. J Pub Econ Theo 13:417–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey B (1997) Not just for the money. An economic theory of personal motivation. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey B (2001) Inspiring economics: human motivation in political economy. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1962) Capitalism and freedom. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama F (1992) The end of history and the last man. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama F (2006) America at the crossroads. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowdy J (1994) Coevolutionary economics: the economy, society and the environment. Springer

  • Harvey B (2005) A brief history of neoliberalism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F (1960) The constitution of liberty. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2015) Conceptualizing Capitalism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hofbauer J, Sigmund K (1998) Evolutionary games and population dynamics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huntington SP (1996) The clash of civilizations. Simon and Schuster, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson MO (2008) Social and economic networks. Princeton University Press, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones G (1980) Social Darwinism and English thought. Humanities Press, Brighton

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. McMillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn H (1944) The idea of nationalism. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Leighton W, Lopez E (2013) Madmen, intellectuals and academic scribblers: the economic engine of political change. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipset S, Marks G (2000) It Didn’t happen here: why socialism failed in the US. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Malerba F, Nelson R, Orsenigo L, Winter S (1999) History-friendly models of Industry evolution: the computer Industry. Ind Corp Chang 8:3–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malerba F, Nelson R, Orsenigo L, Winter S (2001) Competition and industrial policies in a history-friendly model of the evolution of the computer Industry. Int J Ind Organ 19:635–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malerba F, Nelson R, Orsenigo L, Winter S (2008) Public policies and changing boundaries of firms in a history-friendly model of the co-evolution of the computer and semiconductors industries. J Econ Behav Organ 67:355–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malerba F, Nelson R, Orsenigo L, Winter SG (2016) Innovation and the evolution of industries: history-friendly models. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meadows D, Meadows D, Zahn E, Milling P (1972) Limits to growth. Universe Books

  • Metcalfe JS (1998) Evolutionary economics and creative destruction. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell S (1996) Daily life in Victorian England. Greenwood Press, Westport CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery S, Chirot D (2015) The shape of the new. Princeton University Press, NJ

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mosca G (1939) The ruling class. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1990) Institutions, institutional change and economic performance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • North DC, Weingast B (1989) Constitution and commitment: the evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth-century England. J Econ Hist 49:803–832

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Page B, Shapiro RY (1992) The rational public. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Potts J (2007) Evolutionary institutional economics. J Econ Issue 41:341–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodgers DT (2011) Age of fracture. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodrik D (2014) When ideas trump interests: preferences, worldviews and policy innovations. J Econ Perspect 28(1):189–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan RM, Deci EL (2000) Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development and well-being. Am Psychol 55:68–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandholm WH (2010) Population games and evolutionary dynamics. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden-Day, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1999) The possibility of social choice. Am Econ Rev 89:349–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sennett R (1998) The corrosion of character. W.W. Norton, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor AD (2005) Social choice and the mathematics of manipulation. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen, T. (1898) 'Why is economics not an evolutionary science?' Quarterly Journal of Economics, 12(4):373–397

  • Vega-Redondo F (1996) Evolution, games and economic behavior. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vega-Redondo F (2008) Complex social networks. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson P (2000) A terrible beauty: the people and ideas that shaped the modern mind. Weidenfeld and Nicholson, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Weibull JW (1995) Evolutionary game theory. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson O (2000) The new institutional economics: taking stock, looking ahead. J Econ Lit 38:595–613

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Daniel Chirot, J. Stan Metcalfe, Scott Montgomery and Richard R. Nelson for their very helpful comments on previous versions of this work. We also thank two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jason Potts.

Additional information

Supplementary material: https://luis-r-izquierdo.github.io/utopia

The reader can replicate all simulation results presented in this paper by using the computer program provided in the supplementary material. This program can be run using NetLogo (Wilensky, 1999).

Wilensky, U. (1999). NetLogo. http://ccl.northwestern.edu/netlogo/. Center for Connected Learning and Computer-Based Modeling, Northwestern University. Evanston, IL., open source software available at http://ccl.northwestern.edu/netlogo for free.

Appendix

Appendix

In this appendix, we present further insights on the intra-subsystemic dynamics of the model, and on the way these dynamics co-evolve giving rise to the overall dynamics of utopia competition. The exhaustive mathematical exploration of the model goes beyond the scope of this paper. Nevertheless, we want to highlight here some possible lines of progress in the formal exploration; likewise, we present certain results which clarify the mechanisms supporting our socio-economic insights in Section 4. We do not incorporate these results in Section 4 because, perhaps, they might interrupt the history-friendly style of discussion of the paper.

As we show in this Appendix, it is interesting to note that, although we have presented the model as a co-evolution framework that contributes to evolutionary political economy in line with population dynamics thinking, we can use machinery from evolutionary game theory to better understand the dynamics and the results. This is a typical way to proceed in population models (see Weibull 1995; Hofbauer and Sigmund 1998; Sandholm 2010). Thus, in this appendix, we show, firstly, how the intra-subsystem dynamics can be decomposed for future analysis in two extreme subgames and infinite mixes of these subgames. This procedure allows us to better understand the role of parameter φ in the model and in our results (persistence of various co-existing utopias, etc). Afterwards, we consider these insights to reflect on the overall replicator process (expression (3) in Section 3) which is interlinked (in a bi-directional way) in the model with the distinct intra-subsystem replicators (expressions (1) and (2) in Section 3, and the bidirectional links with expression (3)). We present new simulations as supporting material for the socio-economic interpretations in Section 4. The appendix also helps us to pose possible future developments (departing from the current model as a benchmark) as we explain in Section 5.

1.1 Insights on the dynamics of the model

1.1.1 Decomposition of the intra-subsystemic dynamics

Note that the payoff for each level of contribution (eq. (1)) can be written as follows:

$$ \left[\begin{array}{c}{\ u}_{1 t}^{\pi}\\ {}{\ u}_{2 t}^{\pi}\\ {}{\ u}_{3 t}^{\pi}\end{array}\right]=\left({\gamma}_t^{\pi}\left(1-\varphi \right)\left[\begin{array}{ccc}{x}_1& {x}_1& {x}_1\\ {}{x}_2& {x}_2& {x}_2\\ {}{x}_3& {x}_3& {x}_3\end{array}\right]+\varphi \left[\begin{array}{ccc}0& {x}_1& 0\\ {}-{x}_2& 0& {x}_2\\ {}0& -{x}_3& 0\end{array}\right]\right)\left[\begin{array}{c}{s}_{1 t}^{\pi}\\ {}{s}_{2 t}^{\pi}\\ {}{s}_{3 t}^{\pi}\end{array}\right] $$

Thus, at the intra-subsystem level, eq. (2) can be seen as the replicator dynamics of a population game where players are randomly paired to play a 2-player 3-strategy game where the payoff matrix is:

$$ \left({\gamma}_t^{\pi}\left(1-\varphi \right)\left[\begin{array}{ccc}{x}_1& {x}_1& {x}_1\\ {}{x}_2& {x}_2& {x}_2\\ {}{x}_3& {x}_3& {x}_3\end{array}\right]+\varphi \left[\begin{array}{ccc}0& {x}_1& 0\\ {}-{x}_2& 0& {x}_2\\ {}0& -{x}_3& 0\end{array}\right]\right) $$

Let us consider the extreme values of φ. For φ = 0, we have the following game (henceforth SG1, for subgame 1):

$$ {\gamma}_t^{\pi}\left[\begin{array}{ccc}{x}_1& {x}_1& {x}_1\\ {}{x}_2& {x}_2& {x}_2\\ {}{x}_3& {x}_3& {x}_3\end{array}\right] $$

Given that x 1 < x 2 < x 3, strategy 3 is dominant, and evolutionarily stable. Thus, the point s 3 = 1 is asymptotically stable and the system converges to it from any initial condition with s 3 > 0.Footnote 14 The speed of convergence will be faster the greater the value of \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \). Figure 11 below shows the phase portrait of the dynamics of this game in the 2-dimensional simplex.

Fig. 11
figure 11

Phase portrait of the game SG1, with x1 = 0.1, x2 = 0.2, x3 = 0.3, and \( {\upgamma}_{\mathrm{t}}^{\uppi} \)= 0.5. Rest points are shown as red circles

For the other extreme value φ = 1, we have the following game (henceforth SG2, for subgame 2):

$$ \left[\begin{array}{ccc}0& {x}_1& 0\\ {}-{x}_2& 0& {x}_2\\ {}0& -{x}_3& 0\end{array}\right] $$

In SG2, strategy 3 is weakly dominated by strategy 1.Footnote 15 It is not difficult to prove that the rest points of the replicator dynamics for SG2 are:

  1. 1.

    All points in the line s 2 = 0 (and s 3 = 1 − s 1).

  2. 2.

    Point: s 2 = 1. This point is unstable, as it is invadable by strategy 1.

Figure 12 shows the phase portrait of the dynamics of this game in the 2-dimensional simplex.

Fig. 12
figure 12

Phase portrait of the game SG2, with x1 = 0.1, x2 = 0.2, x3 = 0.3. Rest points are shown in red

Therefore, in terms of our model, when φ = 0, and citizens (within their subsystems) are purely partisans (in the sense that they just care about the rise to prevalence of their utopia, without paying attention to possible opportunistic behaviors by their peers in (1)) then, said subsystem tends (in isolated conditions) to a maximum average degree of citizen contribution. On the contrary, when permeability is absolute (as given by φ = 1 in (1)), then citizens perceive (or take advantage of) possible opportunistic behaviors and the subsystem tends to stabilize (in isolated conditions) in the lowest degree of citizen contribution. Of course, we have a continuum of possibilities between subgames 1 and 2, but we can infer that the lower the value of φ in a subsystem, we should tend to obtain higher average levels of commitment in said subsystem. Likewise, when φ is high, then low levels of commitment in the subsystem, or fluctuating paths driven by the ongoing revision of strategies, are expected. In any case, notice that when we couple the subsystems (considering (1), (2) and (3) together in Section 3), then the shares of the subsystems in society also evolve, and the effect of φ in the payoffs gets mediated by endogenously changing subsystem shares, and intra-subsystem behaviors. This much more complex situation is the one we see below.

1.1.2 Insights on the overall dynamics

Taking into consideration the decomposition shown in the previous section, and assuming φ > 0, note that the dynamics of subsystems with very low share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) are driven by SG2, so in such vanishing subsystems eventually strategy 1 becomes dominant, strategy 3 may hold some minor share, and strategy 2 effectively disappears. In the general case, the dynamics of subsystems with a non-negligible share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) will depend on the value of φ.

1.2 Low values of φ

As pointed out above, in subsystems with low share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \), SG2 drives the dynamics, so eventually strategy 1 becomes prevalent, strategy 3 may hold some minor share, and strategy 2 effectively disappears.

In subsystems with high share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \), SG1 drives the dynamics, so strategy 3 is clearly favored, and the greater the value of \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \), the faster the convergence to strategy 3. A greater share s 3 induces an increase in \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \), thus creating a self-reinforcing dynamic.

Which particular subsystem(s) will end up with a significant share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) will depend on initial conditions. A high value of \( {\gamma}_{t=0}^{\pi} \) and, particularly, a high value of \( {s}_{3, t=0}^{\pi} \) will be key. As a representative example, consider Fig. 13, where φ = 0.03.

Fig. 13
figure 13

Representative example of a situation where two subsystems (Group and Nature) coexist. In these two subsystems s 3 ≈ 1, whilst in the subsystems that vanish s 2 ≈ 0 and s 1 is high

1.3 High values of φ

As in the previous case, in subsystems with low share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \), SG2 drives the dynamics. The analysis of the subsystem(s) with significant share \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) is more complicated, as both SG1 and SG2 influence the dynamics. As an example, consider the case where φ = 0.8 and there is a subsystem with \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) ≈ 1. This game shows cyclic dynamics, as can be seen in Fig. 14 (where x1 = 0.3, x2 = 0.45, x3 = 0.6). Figure 15 shows the overall dynamics of a simulation run where the Market subsystem prevails, and its intra-subsystemic dynamics are cyclic.

Fig. 14
figure 14

Phase portrait of a game with (x1, x2 , x3) = (0.3, 0.45, 0.6), φ = 0.8 and \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) = 1. Rest points are shown as red circles. Rest point (1, 0, 0) has associated eigenvalues −0.33 and 0.06; rest point (0, 1, 0) has associated eigenvalues −0.45 and 0.21; rest point (0, 0, 1) has associated eigenvalues −0.06 and 0.33; and finally, interior rest point (0.472, 0.0833, 0.444) has associated eigenvalues 4.58·10−3 ± 0.095i

Fig. 15
figure 15

Representative example of a situation where only one subsystem survives (Market). The intra-subsystemic dynamics of this subsystem are cyclic

1.4 A final example

In intermediate situations where both SG1 and SG2 play a role in the intra-subsystemic dynamics of some subsystems, the overall dynamics can be very different from the extreme cases outlined above. As a final example, consider a model with x1 = 0.3, x2 = 0.45, x3 = 0.6, φ = 0.16, and two subsystems with \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) = 0.5. In this setting, strategy 2 is dominant, and the associated intra-subsystemic dynamics can be seen in Fig. 16.

Fig. 16
figure 16

Phase portrait of a game with (x1, x2 , x3) = (0.3, 0.45, 0.6), φ = 0.16 and \( {\gamma}_t^{\pi} \) = 0.5. Rest points are shown as red circles. Rest point (1, 0, 0) has associated eigenvalues 0.126 and 0.004; rest point (0, 1, 0), which is almost globally stable, has associated eigenvalues −0.054 and −0.036; and finally, rest point (0, 0, 1) has associated eigenvalues −0.126 and 0.038

Figure 17 shows the overall dynamics of a simulation run where the conditions outlined above are approximately met.

Fig. 17
figure 17

Representative example of a situation where two subsystems (Group and Nature) coexist. In these two subsystems s 2 ≈ 1, whilst in the subsystems that vanish s 2 ≈ 0 and s 1 is high

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Almudi, I., Fatas-Villafranca, F., Izquierdo, L.R. et al. The economics of utopia: a co-evolutionary model of ideas, citizenship and socio-political change. J Evol Econ 27, 629–662 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-017-0507-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-017-0507-7

Keywords

JEL classifications

Navigation