Skip to main content
Log in

Ultimate causes and the evolution of altruism

  • Review
  • Published:
Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Reconciling the evolution of altruism with Darwinian natural selection is frequently presented as a fundamental problem in biology. In addition to an exponentially increasing literature on specific mechanisms that can permit altruism to evolve, there has been a recent trend to establish general principles to explain altruism in populations undergoing natural selection. This paper reviews and extends one approach to understanding the ultimate causes underlying the evolution of altruism and mechanisms that can realise them, based on the Price equation. From the Price equation, we can see that such ultimate causes equate to the different ways in which the frequency of an altruistic allele in a population can increase. Under this approach, the ultimate causes underlying the evolution of altruism, given some positive fitness costs and benefits, are positive assortment of altruistic alleles with the altruistic behaviour of others, positive deviations from additive fitness effects when multiple altruists interact or bias in the inheritance of altruistic traits. In some cases, one cause can be interpreted in terms of another. The ultimate causes thus identified can be realised by a number of different mechanisms, and to demonstrate its general applicability, I use the Price equation approach to analyse a number of classical mechanisms known to support the evolution of altruism (or cooperation): repeated interaction, ‘greenbeard’ traits, games played on graphs and payoff synergism. I also briefly comment on other important points for the evolution of altruism, such as the ongoing debate over the predominant status of inclusive fitness as the best way to understand its evolution. I conclude by arguing that analysing the evolution of altruism in terms of its ultimate causes is the logical way to approach the problem and that, despite some of its technical limitations, the Price equation approach is a particularly powerful way of doing so.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although by the 6th edition (p. 86) ‘each [...] profits’ had changed to ‘the community [...] profits’; see Sober (2009).

References

  • Alexander RD (1987) The biology of moral systems. de Gruyter, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R, Hamilton WD (1981) The evolution of cooperation. Science 211(4489):1390

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ, Henrich J (2010) Rapid cultural adaptation can facilitate the evolution of large-scale cooperation. Behav Ecol Sociobiol. doi:10.1007/s00265-010-1100-3

    Google Scholar 

  • Chouard T (2010) Evolution: revenge of the hopeful monster. Nature 463(7283):864

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life, 6th edn. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher JA, Doebeli M (2009). A simple and general explanation for the evolution of altruism. Proc R Soc Lond B 276(1654):13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher JA, Zwick M (2006) Unifying the theories of inclusive fitness and reciprocal altruism. Am Nat 168(2):252–262

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher JA, Zwick M, Doebeli M, Wilson DS (2006) What’s wrong with inclusive fitness? Trends Ecol Evol 21(11):597–598

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Foster KR, Wenseleers T, Ratnieks FLW (2006a) Kin selection is the key to altruism. Trends Ecol Evol 21(2):57–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster KR, Wenseleers T, Ratnieks FLW, Queller DC (2006b) There is nothing wrong with inclusive fitness. Trends Ecol Evol 21(11):599–600

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (1998) Foundations of social evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA, Barton NH (2007) The relation between multilocus population genetics and social evolution theory. Am Nat 169:207–226

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1985) Hamilton’s rule OK. Nature 318:310–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2007) An inclusive fitness analysis of altruism on a cyclical network. J Evol Biol 20(6):2278–2283

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour I and II. J Theor Biol 7:1–52

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1970) Selfish and spiteful behaviour in an evolutionary model. Nature 228(5277):1218–1220

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1975) Innate social aptitudes of man: an approach from evolutionary genetics. In: Fox R (ed) Biosocial anthropology. Malaby, London, pp 133–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi JC, Selten R (1988) A general theory of equilibrium selection in games. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen VAA, van Baalen M (2006) Altruism through beard chromodynamics. Nature 440(7084):663–666

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann L, Keller L (2006) The evolution of cooperation and altruism—a general framework and a classification of models. J Evol Biol 19(5):1365–1376

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann L, Keller L, Sumpter DJ (2007) The evolution of helping and harming on graphs: the return of the inclusive fitness effect. J Evol Biol 20(6):2284–2295

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall JAR, McNamara JM, Houston AI (2010) The state of Darwinian theory. Behav Ecol Sociobiol. doi:10.1007/s00265-010-1121-y

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak MA, May RM (1992) Evolutionary games and spatial chaos. Nature 359:29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak MA, Sigmund K (1998) The dynamics of indirect reciprocity. J Theor Biol 194(4):561–574

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ohtsuki H, Hauert C, Lieberman E, Nowak MA (2006) A simple rule for the evolution of cooperation on graphs. Nature 441(7092):502

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ohtsuki H, Iwasa Y (2004) How should we define goodness? Reputation dynamics in indirect reciprocity. J Theor Biol 231(1):107–120

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227(5257):520–521

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1984) Kin selection and frequency dependence: a game theoretic approach. Biol J Linn Soc 23(2):133–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1985) Kinship, reciprocity and synergism in the evolution of social behaviour. Nature 318(6044):366–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1992) Quantitative genetics, inclusive fitness, and group selection. Am Nat 139(3):540–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1994) Genetic relatedness in viscous populations. Evol Ecol 8(1):70–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratnieks FLW, Foster KR, Wenseleers T (2010) Darwin’s special difficulty: the evolution of ‘neuter’ insects and current theory. Behav Ecol Sociobiol. doi:10.1007/s00265-010-1124-8

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson L (1998) Evolutionary games and equilibrium selection. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2009) Did Darwin write the Origin backwards? Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106(Supplement 1):10048

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ (1985) Soft selection, hard selection, kin selection, and group selection. Am Nat 125:61–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2007) Evolutionary explanations for cooperation. Curr Biol 17(16):661–672

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS, Pollock GB, Dugatkin LA (1992) Can altruism evolve in purely viscous populations? Evol Ecol 6(4):331–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1969) Evolution and the genetics of populations, vol 2. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Zidek JV, van Eeden C (2003) Uncertainty, entropy, variance and the effect of partial information. Lect Notes-Monogr Ser 42:155–167

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank S. Okasha for discussions on causal decomposition and comments on Eq. 5, H. Ohtsuki for clarification of his results concerning the evolution of altruism on graphs, R. Boyd for discussions on his model of cultural evolution in groups, K. Foster and two anonymous reviewers for comments on the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James A. R. Marshall.

Additional information

Communicated by Guest Editor J. McNamara

This contribution is part of the Special Issue ‘Mathematical Models in Ecology and Evolution: Darwin 200’ (see Marshall et al. 2010).

Appendices

Appendix 1: Covariances for repeated interaction model

The expectations we need to calculate our required covariances are:

$${\rm{E}}(G)=g,$$
(27)
$$ \begin{array}{rll} {\rm{E}}(P)&=&{\rm{E}}(P')={\rm{E}}(GP) \\ &=&g(1-g)+g^2 \left(1+\frac{w}{1-w}\right),\end{array} $$
(28)
$${\rm{E}}(GP')=g^2 \left(1+\frac{w}{1-w}\right),$$
(29)

and

$$ \begin{array}{rll}{\rm{E}}(\min(P,P'))&=&{\rm{E}}(G \min(P,P')) \\ &=&g^2 \left(1+\frac{w}{1-w}\right).\end{array} $$
(30)

These expectations give the following covariances:

$$ \begin{array}{rll}&&{\rm{Cov}}(G,P) \\ &&=(1-g)\left(g(1-g)+g^2\left(1+\frac{w}{1-w}\right)\right), \end{array}$$
(31)
$${\rm{Cov}}(G,P')=(1-g)g^2\left(\frac{w}{1-w}\right),$$
(32)

and

$${\rm{Cov}}(G,\min(P,P'))=(1-g)g^2\left(1+\frac{w}{1-w}\right).$$
(33)

Appendix 2: Expectations for Greenbeard model

The required expectations for the greenbeard model can be calculated as:

$${\rm{E}}(G)={\rm{E}}(G')=g, $$
(34)
$${\rm{E}}(Q)={\rm{E}}(Q')=q, $$
(35)
$${\rm{E}}(GG'Q)=g^2 {\rm{P}}(\textrm{greenbeard} | \textrm{altruist}), $$
(36)

and

$${\rm{E}}(G'Q)={\rm{E}}(GQ')={\rm{E}}(G^2Q')=qg. $$
(37)

Appendix 3: Expectations for graph model

To calculate the required expectations for the ‘death-birth’ model of altruism on graphs, we begin by calculating the expected genotype of the actors competing for reproduction, and the unconditioned expected genotype of their neighbours,

$${\rm{E}}(G)={\rm{E}}(G')=g. $$
(38)

To calculate the joint expectation E(GG′) required to determine Cov(G,G′) it would seem we should be able to directly apply Eq. 16, however this would be incorrect, as we must take account of the fact that all competitors interacted with a common neighbour in determining their payoff, the site being replaced. This focal site is an altruist with probability g, otherwise it is a defector. Thus, we modify Eq. 16 to calculate the joint expectation of G and G′ as

$$ \begin{array}{rll}{\rm{E}}(GG')&=&{\rm{E}}(G'|G=1) \\ &=&\frac{g}{k} + \frac{k-1}{k}\left(g+\frac{1-g}{k-1} \right), \end{array} $$
(39)

where the first term is the expected genotype of the site being replaced, and the second term is the conditional expectation of Eq. 16, weighted by the remaining proportion of neighbours (k − 1)/k. The variance and covariance presented in the main text follow directly from the above results.

Appendix 4: Analysis of synergism model

The expectations required for the synergism model are:

$${\rm{E}}(G)={\rm{E}}\left(G^2\right)=g, $$
(40)

and

$${\rm{E}}(GG')={\rm{E}}\left(G^2G'\right)=g^2, $$
(41)

As mentioned in the main text, it is of interest to briefly note that frequency-dependent social dilemmas such as the stag hunt are often referred to as having ‘risk dominant’ and ‘payoff dominant’ equilibria (Harsanyi and Selten 1988). These refinements of the Nash equilibrium concept arose in classical game theory. In evolutionary game theory, under the replicator dynamics for example, equilibrium selection is frequency-dependent, and a ‘risk dominant’ equilibrium can be defined as that having the greatest basin of attraction (Samuelson 1998), but the covariance approach naturally captures uncertainty and thus might provide a different and interesting perspective. For example a partial simplification from Eq. 20 to Eq. 24 could be written

$${\rm{Var}}(G)d>{\rm{E}}(1-G)c, $$
(42)

where G is the random variable corresponding to the population frequency of stag hunters, p. Thus, the risk-dominant stag hunting equilibrium can be thought of as being favoured when the variance (i.e. the uncertainty (Zidek and van Eeden 2003)) in the synergistic benefit from both individuals cooperating, exceeds the magnitude of the cost of altruism multiplied by the expected frequency of non-cooperators.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Marshall, J.A.R. Ultimate causes and the evolution of altruism . Behav Ecol Sociobiol 65, 503–512 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00265-010-1110-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00265-010-1110-1

Keywords

Navigation