Skip to main content
Log in

Analytic radicalism

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Constitutional Political Economy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Brennan and Hamlin provide a normative justification for dispositional conservatism based on the concave value functions which give rise to quasi-risk aversion. This note modifies this argument for “analytic conservatism” by allowing jurisdictional exit in response to institutional decline. By providing a welfare floor which limits the cost of failure, exit reverses the normative implications of Brennan and Hamlin’s argument, making risk-neutral agents quasi-risk seeking and justifying a radical disposition to reform under some circumstances.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For other rational choice discussions of institutional conservatism, see Congleton (2011) and Kuran (1988).

  2. On political dispositions, see generally Hamlin (2006).

  3. Brennan and Buchanan’s (1981, 1983, 1985, pp. 54–59) earlier arguments for systematically pessimistic assumptions regarding human nature for comparative institutional analysis are logically similar to Brennan and Hamlin’s argument for analytic radicalism. My use of the term “quasi-risk aversion” comes from Brennan and Buchanan (1985, p. 54).

  4. An agent has convex preferences over some set of goods if averages are preferred to extremes. More precisely, preferences are convex in case any bundle which is a weighted average of two bundles on the same indifference curve is at least at valued as either of the original bundles.

  5. Brennan and Hamlin contrast conservatism with “idealism.” I avoid that term here because their conceptualization of idealism is focused very much on a desire to reach some ideal point rather than on institutional change generally. An acceptable alternative to “radicalism” for my purposes would be “progressivism.”

  6. For example, indivisibilities in consumption can produce increasing marginal utility of income over certain ranges where a continuous function would produce uniform diminishing returns. This might explain the allegedly irrational practice of simultaneously buying lottery tickets and insurance (Friedman and Savage 1948; Kwang 1965).

  7. People move for many reasons, but institutional factors do seem to be a factor in locational decisions. See Dowding et al. (1994) for an overview of the empirical evidence.

  8. Becker and Posner (2005) use similar logic to explain apparently risk-seeking behaviour on the part of the extremely poor and unhappy, with the option of suicide providing a welfare floor.

  9. It’s important to note that such preferences are massively over-determined and that an efficiency justification is not necessarily a causal explanation.

References

  • Becker, G. S., & Posner, R. A. (2005). Suicide and risk-taking: An economic approach. Working paper, Illinois: University of Chicago.

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1981). The normative purpose of economic ‘science’: Rediscovery of an eighteenth-century method. International Review of Law and Economics, 1(2), 155–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1983). Predictive power and the choice among regimes. The Economic Journal, 93(369), 89–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (2004). Analytic conservatism. British Journal of Political Science, 34(4), 675–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (2006). Conservatism, idealism and cardinality. Analysis, 66(292), 286–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, E. (1790). Reflections on the Revolution in France. London: J. Dodsley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2011). Perfecting parliament: Constitutional reform, liberalism, and the rise of western democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowding, K., John, P., & Biggs, S. (1994). Tiebout: A survey of the empirical literature. Urban Studies, 31(4–5), 767–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. J. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy, 56(4), 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, A. (2006). Political dispositions and dispositional politics. In G. Eusepi & A. Hamlin (Eds.), Beyond conventional economics: The limits of rational behaviour in political decision making (pp. 3–16). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, A. O. (1970). Exit, voice, and loyalty. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuran, T. (1988). The tenacious past: Theories of personal and collective conservatism. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 10(2), 143–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwang, N. Y. (1965). Why do people buy lottery tickets? Choices involving risk and the indivisibility of expenditure. Journal of Political Economy, 73(5), 530–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1947). Rationalism in politics. Cambridge Journal, 1(81–98), 145–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1962). Rationalism in politics and other essays. London: Methuen.

  • Tiebout, C. M. (1956). A pure theory of local expenditures. The Journal of Political Economy, 64(5), 416–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V., & Kerber, W. (1994). Institutional competition among jurisdictions: An evolutionary approach. Constitutional Political Economy, 5(2), 193–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihanto, M. (1992). Competition between local governments as a discovery procedure. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 148(3), 411–436.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Geoffrey Brennan, Keith Dowding, Patri Friedman, Michael Miller, the editors, and an anonymous reviewer for their comments and suggestions. The usual discalimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brad Taylor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Taylor, B. Analytic radicalism. Const Polit Econ 24, 166–172 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-013-9134-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10602-013-9134-y

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation