Skip to main content
Log in

Augmented reality, augmented ethics: who has the right to augment a particular physical space?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Ethics and Information Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Augmented reality (AR) blends the virtual and physical worlds such that the virtual content experienced by a user of AR technology depends on the user’s geographical location. Games such as Pokémon GO and technologies such as HoloLens are introducing an increasing number of people to augmented reality. AR technologies raise a number of ethical concerns; I focus on ethical rights surrounding the augmentation of a particular physical space. To address this I distinguish public and private spaces; I also separate the case where we access augmentations via many different applications from the case where there is a more unified sphere of augmentation. Private property under a unified sphere of augmentation is akin to physical property; owners retain the right to augment their property and prevent others from augmenting it. Private property with competing apps is more complex; it is not clear that owners have a general right to prevent augmentations in this case, assuming those augmentations do not interfere with the owner’s use of the property. I raise several difficult cases, such as augmenting a daycare with explicit sexual or violent images. Public property with competing apps is relatively straightforward, and most augmentation is ethical; those apps simply function like different guidebooks. Under a unified sphere of augmentation it is unclear whether augmentations should be treated more like public speech (which we value) or graffiti (which we do not) or (most likely) some of each. Further consideration is needed to determine what kinds of augmentations we view as ethical.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Data sharing not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.

Notes

  1. As Brinkman (2014) notes, this makes augmented reality somewhat different than head’s up displays (which may project information but do not adapt to the world), location-aware applications such as Google Maps (which track the user’s location but do not project virtual information), and apps that do image processing (which may recognize that an image is of a particular subject but again does not project that information onto the world.) Augmented reality requires both the projection on to the world and the analysis of surroundings in order to adapt or change those projections.

  2. See Wolf et al. (2015) for further discussion of these technologies.

  3. There is some interesting work being done on this kind of augmentation—see, e.g., Narumi et al. (2011)—but it is still relatively rare compared to visual or haptic augmentation.

  4. This vision of a unified sphere of augmentation may lead to problems when we try to figure out how to integrate multiple applications or systems; Roesner et al. (2014) discuss how the implementation of augmented reality technologies may pose security and privacy concerns.

  5. Perhaps the most worrying scenario for many people is the idea that AR could be combined with facial recognition technology so that information about strangers could be displayed to a user as he or she was walking down the street; this would greatly erode public anonymity. Acquisti et al. (2014) created a very basic version of this, so the concern is well-founded.

  6. Note that there could be circumstances where these actions are ethical; I could confiscate your pencil if you refuse to stop filling out an exam paper once the time has expired, say, and that would likely be ethical. Similarly, if I knew some maniac was going to shoot the next person who wrote a sentence with that pencil, it would probably excuse coating it in grease to prevent you from being shot (although this is likely not the most efficient way of preventing this occurrence.) These would both count as extenuating circumstances.

  7. Note that some objects can be obtained for real world currency, in which case the manner of obtaining them is not purely virtual.

  8. Of course, since most virtual worlds are hosted by private companies and players simply operate under an End User License Agreement, there is a good chance that technically they do not own the virtual property. How to handle this legally is a matter of much debate. (Cifrino 2014; Glushko 2007; Horowitz 2007; Nelson 2011) However, the fact that the company could decide that a player should not have access to a particular item (perhaps because it was obtained by violating the Terms of Service) is rather different from saying that another player can ethically take it. A player may not own an item or a piece of virtual property, exactly, but it is still intended to be used by that player and thus she may be harmed by its removal. The ethics seem somewhat more straightforward than the law in this case.

  9. Obviously this is a little simplistic; a blog that uses your name for its URL is easier to find than a random string of characters. However, the content itself in general does not depend on the URL. There are a few exceptions to this—for instance, if http://howdovaccinescauseautism.com/ lost its domain, the content of the page might have to be changed. But it could probably survive a minor alteration (howdovaccinesleadtoautism.com, perhaps) without requiring a content change. This is different from augmenting a physical space, where the virtual content is tied much more tightly to the specific geographic location.

  10. There is also a difference with intellectual property, which generally does not have a physical or virtual location of this sort; you do not have to be in a particular virtual world or in a particular part of the physical world to experience it.

  11. Brinkman (2014) notes that we frequently use metaphors to describe technology, which can be problematic when the metaphor breaks down because there is not a strong enough parallel between the cases. Nevertheless, with the restriction to private property and a single sphere of augmentation, I believe the metaphor holds here.

  12. I would note that there are many reasons why I might wish to prevent the augmentation of my property in addition to grumpiness. For instance, an augmentation could interfere with the intended use of a property; this could have serious consequences in certain cases. Thus a hospital might wish to prevent unwanted augmentations from appearing in order to keep surgeons from being distracted, say. Similarly, a daycare center might not wish to have graphic depictions of violence augmenting their space, as it might discourage parents from entrusting their children to the center.

  13. Of course, the state’s use may trump my use, such as if the road is going to be closed and road closure signs rest partially on my property; in that case, my use is subordinate to the greater good.

  14. At least at present. While this response to dealing with augmentations—sometimes called “geofencing” because it places a digital “fence” around the particular geographical area (Brinkman 2014)—seems to align well with current ethical intuitions about property, Wassom (2015) discusses the fact that ultimately we might sell physical and digital development rights separately for something like a commercial space.

  15. This would also hold true if the augmentation enticed people to trespass, as Wassom (2015) notes.

  16. Though possibly legal, unless it rises to the level of defamation.

  17. Again, assuming that the information was not gleaned unethically.

  18. This would need to be designed carefully and with informed consent in mind. As one of my reviewers pointed out, we have standards for public indecency which prevents certain things from occurring in view of all people—this would likely prevent this case from occurring under a single sphere of augmentation. If the app were aimed at adults and clearly presented what content users could expect, thus ensuring informed consent from its users, then I believe this objection could be sidestepped for AR that is spread across many different apps.

  19. There have also been issues with people playing Pokémon GO in hospitals, as one of my reviewers noted. In general these cases involve players either using cell phones where they are not permitted or entering restricted areas in search of Pokémon. I chose not to focus on these cases because they strike me as somewhat less straightforward than the Holocaust Museum case; one could argue that the unethical action is in the forbidden cell phone use or the entering of restricted areas by itself, ignoring the augmented reality aspect completely.

  20. Perhaps it could be possible to make temporally-limited augmentations such that they expire after a certain period of time. This could at least cut down on the number of overlapping augmentations in a particular place.

  21. There’s also an interesting question about whether there might be good reason to prevent augmentation of a particular space even if the augmentation itself is not problematic. For instance, perhaps a piece of public art should be experienced as it is, rather than having people view its augmentations and thus experience it only through the lens of pre-conceived notions.

References

  • Acquisti, A., Gross, R., & Stutzman, F. (2014). Face recognition and privacy in the age of augmented reality. Journal of Privacy and Confidentiality, 6(2), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blizzard Entertainment. (2004). World of warcraft. Irvine: Blizzard Entertainment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinkman, B. (2014). Ethics and pervasive augmented reality: Some challenges and approaches. In K. D. Pimple (Ed.), Emerging pervasive information and communication technologies (PICT): Ethical challenges, opportunities and safeguards (pp. 149–175). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cifrino, C. J. (2014). Virtual property, virtual rights: Why contract law, not property law, must be the governing paradigm in the law of virtual worlds. Boston College Law Review, 55(1), 235–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainow, B. (2014). Ethics in emerging technology. Itnow, 56(3), 16–18. https://doi.org/10.1093/itnow/bwu067.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doshi, A., Smith, R. T., Thomas, B. H., & Bouras, C. (2016). Use of projector based augmented reality to improve manual spot-welding precision and accuracy for automotive manufacturing. The International Journal of Advanced Manufacturing Technology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00170-016-9164-5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feng, S., Caire, R., Cortazar, B., Turan, M., Wong, A., & Ozcan, A. (2014). Immunochromatographic diagnostic test analysis using Google Glass. ACS Nano, 8(3), 3069–3079. https://doi.org/10.1021/nn500614k.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., & Kahn, P. H. (2000). New directions: A value-sensitive design approach to augmented reality. In DARE 2000: Design of Augmented Reality Environments, Elsinore, Denmark (pp. 163–164). New York: ACM.

  • Glushko, B. (2007). Tales of the (Virtual) city: Governing property disputes in virtual worlds. Berkeley Technology Law Journal, 22(1), 507–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, S. J. (2007). Competing lockean claims to virtual property. Harvard Journal of Law & Technology, 20(2), 443–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linden Research Inc. (2003). Second life. San Francisco: Linden Research Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1689/1988). Two treatises of government (3rd edn.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narumi, T., Nishizaka, S., Kajinami, T., Tanikawa, T., & Hirose, M. (2011). Augmented reality flavors: Gustatory display based on edible marker and cross-modal interaction. Paper presented at the Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems, Vancouver, BC, Canada.

  • Nelson, J. W. (2011). A virtual property solution: How privacy law can protect the citizens of virtual worlds. Oklahoma City University Law Review, 36(2), 395–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niantic Inc. (2016). Pokémon GO. San Francisco: Niantic Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, A. (2016). Holocaust Museum to visitors: Please stop catching Pokémon here. The Washington Post.

  • Roesner, F., Kohno, T., & Molnar, D. (2014). Security and privacy for augmented reality systems. Communications of the ACM, 57(4), 88–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1762/1997). The social contract. In V. Gourevitch (Ed.), The social contract and other later political writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strikwerda, L. (2012). Theft of virtual items in online multiplayer computer games: An ontological and moral analysis. Ethics and Information Technology, 14, 89–97. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-011-9285-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strikwerda, L. (2014). Should virtual cybercrime be regulated by means of criminal law? A philosophical, legal-economic, pragmatic and constitutional dimension. Information & Communications Technology Law, 23(1), 31–60. https://doi.org/10.1080/13600834.2014.891870.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wassom, B. D. (2015). Augmented reality law, privacy, and ethics: Law, society, and emerging AR technologies. Waltham: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, M. J., Grodzinsky, F., & Miller, K. (2015). Augmented reality all around us: Power and perception at a crossroads. ACM Computers and Society, 45(3), 126–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erica L. Neely.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that she has no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Neely, E.L. Augmented reality, augmented ethics: who has the right to augment a particular physical space?. Ethics Inf Technol 21, 11–18 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-018-9484-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-018-9484-2

Keywords

Navigation