Skip to main content
Log in

Collective Responsibility and the Career Military Officer’s Right to Public Dissent

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Current norms among professional military officers that govern obedience and dissent strongly discourage officers from offering public criticism of policy enacted by civilian authorities, even if that policy is immoral, illegal, or unconstitutional. We identify a set of circumstances that create a moral imperative for an officer to take action and we leverage prevailing ethical guidelines to argue that in certain cases, even individual officers not directly involved in the execution of the policy have moral standing to offer public criticism of it. We consider the consequences of relaxing norms prohibiting public dissent and explore the trade-off between tolerating immoral policy and the likelihood of mistakenly criticizing appropriate policy. Finally, we offer evidence that current military-civilian relations in the United States are such that placing higher value on dissent would benefit professional military officers and may improve policy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Moten (2009) for a thorough discussion of the dispute between General Eric Shinseki, Army Chief of Staff, and Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld in 2003 over the appropriate number of troops with which to invade Iraq.

  2. See Joint Staff (Joint Staff 2001) for doctrinal definitions of these terms.

  3. For elaboration on this point, see Seagren (2015, pg. 183-185).

  4. A Lieutenant Commander typically has between ten to twenty years of commissioned service, and are effectively mid-level officers. The rank is equivalent to that of of Major in the Marine Corps, Army, and Air Force.

  5. For links to this memorandum and others, see New York Times’ “Guide to the Memos on torture”, found at: https://archive.nytimes.com/www.nytimes.com/ref/international/24MEMO-GUIDE.html? Last accessed: 21 April 2018

  6. Army Chief of Staff during WWII, General George Marshall, is credited by many as the paragon of the non-partisan officer of this era and the fact that he did not vote was widely known. See Kohn Kohn (2009) and Corbett and Davidson Corbett and Davidson (2009) for discussions of the norm among officers to abstain from voting in elections.

References

  • Abdel-Nour F (2003) National responsibility. Polit Theory 31(5):693–719

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alkadry MG, Witt MT (2009) Abu Ghraib and the normalization of torture and hate. Public Integr 11(2):135–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angeles RE (2013) Military dissent: what are the ethical implications of tensions in us civil-military relations? US Army War College

  • Becker J, Shane S (2012) Secret ‘kill list’ proves a test of Obama’s principles and will. New York Times

  • Brooks RA (2009) Militaries and political activity in democracies. In: Nielson S, Snider D (eds) American civil-military relations: The Soldier and the State in a New Era. Johns Hopkins University Press, pp 213–38

  • Burk J (2002) Theories of democratic civil-military relations. Armed Forces Soc 29(1):7–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiu RK (2003) Ethical judgment and whistleblowing intention: examining the moderating role of locus of control. J Bus Eth 43(1-2):65–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chokshi N (2016) My conscious bothered me: army captain sues Obama over illegal war on islamic state. The Washington Post

  • Clausewitz CV (1976) On war. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman S (2009) The problems of duty and loyalty. J Mil Ethics 8(2):105–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook ML (2008) Revolt of the generals: a case study in professional ethics. Parameters 38(1):4–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbett S, Davidson MJ (2009) The role of the military in presidential politics. Parameters 39(4):58–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford NC (2007) Individual and collective moral responsibility for systemic military atrocity. J Polit Philos 15(2):187–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davion V (2006) Health care in the united states: evil intentions and collective responsibility. Midwest Stud Philos 30(1):325–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Department of Defense (2006) The Armed Forces Officer. United States Government

  • Elliston FA (1982) Civil disobedience and whistleblowing: a comparative appraisal of two forms of dissent. J Bus Eth 1(1):23–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epps G (2015) The war the congress won’t declare. The Atlantic

  • Feaver P (1996) The civil-military problematique: Huntington, Janowitz, and the question of civilian control. Armed Forces Soc 23(2):149–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feaver P (2003) Armed servants: agency, oversight, and civil-military relations. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J (1968) Collective responsibility. J Philos 65(21):674–688

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Firth R (1952) Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer. Philos Phenomenol Res 12(3):317–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishback I (2005) A matter of honor. Washington Post

  • French PA (1973) Individual and collective responsibility: the massacre at My Lai. Schenkman

  • French PA (1984) Corporate and collective responsibility. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson BW (2012) The need for proper military dissent. US Army War College

  • Hayek FA (1944) The Road to Serfdom. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh S (2004) Torture at Abu Ghraib: American soldiers brutalized iraqis. The New Yorker

  • Huntington SP (1957) The soldier and the state: the theory and politics of civil-military relations. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Janowitz M (1961) The professional soldier: a social and political portrait. The Free Press

  • Jensen JV (1987) Ethical tension points in whistleblowing. J Bus Eth 6(4):321–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joint Staff (2001) Joint Publication 1-02:Department of Defense Dictionary of Military and Associated Terms. United States Government

  • Jubb PB (1999) Whistleblowing: a restrictive definition and interpretation. J Bus Eth 21(1):77–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiel JL (2007) When soldiers speak out: a survey of provisions limiting freedom of speech in the military. Parameters 37(3):69–82

    Google Scholar 

  • King ML (1963) Letter from birmingham city jail

  • Kohn RH (2009) Building trust: civil-military behaviors for effective national security. In: Nielson S, Snider D (eds) American civil-military relations: The Soldier and the State in a New Era. Johns Hopkins University Press, pp 264–289

  • Koven SG (2009) Separation of powers, rule of law, and the bush administration. Public Integr 11(4):347–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutz C (2000) Complicity: ethics and law for a collective age. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis H (1948) Collective responsibility. Philosophy 24:3–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis NA (2003) Red cross criticizes indefinite detention in guantanamo bay. New York Times

  • May L (1987) The Morality of Groups

  • Mazzetti M (2014) Senate panel faults cia over brutality and deciet in terrorism interrogations. The New York Times, pp A1

  • McGary H (1986) Morality and collective liability. J Value Inq 20(2):157–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milburn AR (2010) Breaking ranks: dissent and the military professional. Joint Force Quarterly, pp 101–107

  • Miller Z (2014) Obama: ‘we tortured some folks’. Time

  • Moten M (2009) A broken dialogue: Rumsfeld, Shinseki, and civil-military tension. In: Nielson S, Snider D (eds) American civil-military relations: the Soldier and the State in a New Era. Johns Hopkins University Press, pp 42–71

  • Narveson J (2002) Collective responsibility. J Ethics 6(2):179–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newbold G (2006) Why iraq was a mistake. TIME

  • Pfiffner JP (2005) Torture and public policy. Public Integr 7(4):313–329

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest D, Smith RJ (2004) Memo offered justification for use of torture. Washington Post

  • Reed GE (2014) Expressing loyal dissent: moral considerations from literature on followership. Public Integr 17(1):5–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinke SJ (2006) Abu Ghraib a case of moral and administrative failure. Public Integr 8(2):135–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risen J, Lichtblau E (2005) Bush lets us spy on callers without courts. New York Times

  • Roush P (2008) Constitutional ethics. In: Lucas G, Rubel WR (eds) Ethics and the military profession: the moral foundations of leadership. Pearson Education, pp 79–86

  • Sappington DE (1991) Incentives in principal-agent relationships. J Econ Perspect 5(1):45–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage C (2011) 2 top lawyers lost to Obama in libya war policy debate. The New York Times

  • Savage C, Baker P (2013) Obama, in a shift, to limit targets of drone strikes. The New York Times

  • Savage C (2016) An army captain takes Obama to court over isis fight. The New York Times

  • Seagren CW (2015) Military ethics and moral blame across agency lines. J Mil Ethics 14(2):177–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shahinpoor N, Matt BF (2007) The power of one: dissent and organizational life. J Bus Eth 74(1):37–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shane L (2010) ’Birther’ sentenced to six months in prison, kicked out of army. Stars & Stripes

  • Smith A (1976) The theory of moral sentiments. DD Raphael & AL MacFie (éd), 6e éd(1790), The Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith

  • Snider D M (2008) Dissent and strategic leadership of the military professions. Orbis 52(2):256–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snow NE (2009) How ethical theory can improve practice: lessons from Abu Ghraib. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 12(5):555–568

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stilz A (2011) Collective responsibility and the state. J Polit Philos 19(2):190–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strausz R (1997) Collusion and renegotiation in a principal–supervisor–agent relationship. Scand J Econ 99(4):497–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tirole J (1986) Hierarchies and bureaucracies: on the role of collusion in organizations. J Law Econ Organ 2(2):181–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber J (1993) Institutionalizing ethics into business organizations: a model and research agenda. Bus Ethics Q 3(04):419–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank Stephen Trainor, John Bauer, David Henderson, Matthew Larkin, Melissa Martin, and John Chapman for helpful comments on and discussion of various concepts contained in older drafts on this topic. The views and opinions expressed in this article are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the official policy or position of any agency of the U.S. Government.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chad W. Seagren.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Seagren, C.W. Collective Responsibility and the Career Military Officer’s Right to Public Dissent. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 22, 41–59 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-09977-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-09977-7

Keywords

Navigation