Skip to main content
Log in

Civil Disobedience, Not Merely Conscientious Objection, In Medicine

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Those arguing that conscientious objection in medicine should be declared unethical by professional societies face the following challenge: conscientious objection can function as an important reforming mechanism when it involves health care workers refusing to participate in certain medical interventions deemed standard of care and legally sanctioned but which undermine patients’ rights. In such cases, the argument goes, far from being unethical, conscientious objection may actually be a professional duty. I examine this sort of challenge and ultimately argue that these acts of conscience done in the interest of reforming professional norms or medical regulations are best understood as episodes of civil disobedience rather than episodes of conscientious objection. In contrast to the private, exempting nature of conscientious objection, civil disobedience is a public breach of a norm or law undertaken with the aim of bringing about a change in governmental policies or professional standards. Consequently, clinicians may have a duty to engage in civil disobedience even while professional societies are right to declare limitations on the ethical appropriateness of conscientious objection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is a problem even without establishing that patients have a positive right to medical services [that is, a right to receive any medically appropriate service from the clinician of one’s choice]. Insofar as our society allows for access to healthcare to be determined by one’s financial situation or medical savvy, we are reinforcing an objectionable form of social hierarchy. Even in the absence of a positive right to health care, allowing for inequity in access is arguably unjust since it expresses unequal respect and concern for all citizens. On this point see (Anderson 1999).

  2. It should be noted that Savulescu claims that insofar physicians are working in private practice, they “have more liberty to offer the service of their choice, based on their values” just as long as patients are fully informed of the alternatives they can receive elsewhere (2006, p. 296). This distinction between private and public, presumably works in a system where most people access their healthcare publicly and so only seek out private medicine electively. It is unclear whether his lenience toward private practice would remain in a healthcare system like the US.

  3. Adapted from Smith and Brownlee (2017, pp. 14–15). See also, (Wicclair 2011, p. 33).

  4. A notable exception among defenders is Mark Wicclair, who argues for a “compromise approach” in which professional obligations justify several constraints on the exercise of conscience by clinicians, as long as the health care professionals do not violate these constraints they can exercise their conscience while fulfilling their core professional obligations. On Wicclair’s account, the Incompatibility Thesis is understood as the analogue to “Conscience Absolutism”; both of which are polar extreme positions that are not well founded in ethical discourse or professional practice. I disagree that the incompatibility thesis is so extreme as I go onto argue. This disagreement may lie in the fact that Wicclair understands the incompatibility thesis as entailing the stronger Unfit for Profession Thesis whereas I think the two theses can be pulled apart. See, in particular, Wicclair ( 2011, p. 91).

  5. I am grateful to Abraham Nussbaum for our personal discussion about some of the details of this case in a panel at the Ohio State University on February 26, 2018.

  6. Whether HB 854 is indeed a legitimately developed and constitutional piece of legislation is a live question. For the purposes of this paper, let us assume that it is an unjust law, created by legitimate means.

  7. For the research conducted in the 50s and 60s under John Money (see Money et al. 1955; 1957).

  8. In this way, FD differs from one of Wicclair’s interesting lines of defense of Conscientious Objection (see Wicclair 2011, especially p. 50).

  9. For further discussion of see also, Childress (1985) and Wicclair (2011, pp. 11–13).

References

  • Alexander, J. K. (2005). Promising, professional obligations, and the refusal to provide service. HEC Forum, 17(3), 178–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Medical Association. (2020). Physician exercise of conscience. AMA Code of Medical Opinion 1.1.7. https://www.ama-assn.org/delivering-care/ethics/physician-exercise-conscience. Accessed 25 June 2020.

  • American Pharmacists Association. (1994). Code of ethics for pharmacists. https://www.pharmacist.com/code-ethics. Accessed 13 August 2020.

  • American Pharmacists Association. 2004. Pharmacist's concience clause. APhA Policy Manual. https://www.pharmacist.com/policy-manual?key=pharmacist%20conscience%20clause. Accessed 13 August 2020. 

  • Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109(2), 287–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson N. (2006). Pharmacists with no Plan B. Christianity Today. https://www.christianitytoday.com/ct/2006/august/31.44.html?ctlredirect=true. Accessed 13 August 2020.

  • Brock, D. (2008). Conscientious refusal by physicians and pharmacists: Who is obligated to do what, and why? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 29(3), 187–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchbinder, M., Lassiter, D., Mercier, R., Bryant, A., & Drapkin Lyerly, A. (2016). Reframing conscientious care: Providing abortion care when law and conscience collide. Hastings Center Report, 46(2), 22–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charo, R. A. (2005). The celestial fire of conscience – Refusing to deliver medical care. New England Journal of Medicine, 352(24), 2471–2473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, M. (2012). Conscience clauses, the refusal to treat, and civil disobedience—Practicing medicine as a Christian in a hostile secular moral space. Christian Bioethics, 18(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Childress, J. (1985). Civil disobedience, conscientious objection, and evasive noncompliance: A framework for the analysis and assessment of illegal actions in health care. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 10(1), 63–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clendinen D. (2003). Dr. John Fryer, 65, psychiatrist who said in 1972 he was gay. New York Times, March 5, 2003. https://www.nytimes.com/2003/03/05/us/dr-john-fryer-65-psychiatrist-who-said-in-1972-he-was-gay.html. Accessed 13 August 2020.

  • Creighton, S. (2001). Surgery for intersex. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 94(5), 218–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickens, B. (2009). Legal protection and the limits of conscientious objection: When conscientious objection is unethical. Medicine and Law, 28, 337–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiala, C., & Arthur, J. (2014). ’Dishonorable Disobedience’—Why refusal to treat reproductive healthcare is not conscientious objection. Psychosomatic Gynaecology and Obstetrics, 1(1), 12–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (2019). The Scoundrel and the visionary: On reasonable hope and the possibility of a just future. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 27(3), 294–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameton, A. (1984). Nursing practice: The ethical issues. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, M. L., Jr. (1994). Letter from the Birmingham jail. San Francisco: Harper San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, M., & Drapkin, L. A. (2013). The limits of conscientious refusal: A duty to ensure access. Virtual Mentor AMA Journal of Ethics, 15(3), 257–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Money, J., Hampson, J. G., & Hampson, J. L. (1955). Hermaphroditism: Recommendations concerning assignment of sex, change of sex and psychologic management. Bulletin of the Johns Hopkins Hospital, 97(4), 284–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Money, J., Hampson, J. G., & Hampson, J. L. (1957). Imprinting and the establishment of gender role. Archives of Neurology Psychiatry, 77(3), 333–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Women’s Law Center. (2010). Pharmacy Refusals 101. Resource Document. https://nwlc.org/sites/default/files/pdfs/pharmacyrefusals101.410.pdf . Accessed 13 August 2020.

  • Noesen v. State of Wisconsin Department of Regulation and Licensing, Pharmacy Examining Board, 751 N.W.2d 385 (Wis. 2008).

  • Nussbaum, M. (2006). Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, Mass: The Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2004). Hope and its place in mind. Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 592(1), 152–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Rushton, C., Batcheller, J., Schroeder, K., & Donohue, P. (2015). Burnout and resilience among nurses practicing in high-intensity settings. American Journal of Critical Care, 24(5), 412–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. (2006). Conscientious objection in medicine. BMJ, 332(7536), 294–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuklenk, U., & Smalling, R. (2017). Why medical professionals have no moral claim to conscientious objection accommodation in liberal democracies. Journal of Medical Ethics, 43(4), 234–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1973). Democracy and disobedience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. (2013). Civil disobedience and deliberative democracy. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W., & Brownlee, K. (2017). Civil disobedience and conscientious objection. Oxford research encyclopedia of politicshttps://oxfordre.com/politics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-114?rskey=GHId3k&result=1. Accessed 15 August 2020. 

  • Stahl, R., & Emanuel, E. (2017). Physicians, not conscripts – Conscientious objection in healthcare. New England Journal of Medicine, 376(14), 1380–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sulmasy, D. P. (2008). What is conscience, and why is respect for it so important? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 29(3), 135–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicclair, M. (2000). Conscientious objection in medicine. Bioethics, 14(3), 205–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicclair, M. (2011). Conscientious objection in health care: An ethical analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dana Howard.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Howard, D. Civil Disobedience, Not Merely Conscientious Objection, In Medicine. HEC Forum 33, 215–232 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-020-09417-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-020-09417-5

Navigation