Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemological Misgivings of Karen Barad’s ‘Posthumanism’

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Karen Barad develops a view she calls ‘posthumanism,’ or ‘agential realism,’ where the human is reconfigured away from the central place of explanation, interpretation, intelligibility, and objectivity to make room for the epistemic importance of other material agents. Barad is not alone in this kind of endeavor, but her posthumanism offers a unique epistemological position. Her aim is to take a performative rather than a representationalist approach to analyzing ‘socialnatural’ practices and challenge methodological assumptions that may go unnoticed in some disciplinary fields. Yet for all the good of the challenge, Barad must support it with sound epistemological theorizing, theorizing that would apply to any methodology, whether that be sociological, historical, anthropological, or philosophical. Thus, where one might critique Barad on her assessments of sociological, historical, or anthropological incorporations of humans and the nonhuman, I critique Barad’s epistemology on its sense of objectivity and dismissal of the centrality of the human. I argue that Barad’s epistemology must retain a particular form of humanism, a humanism that stakes human subjectivity as the locus of rationality and objectivity, without which it creates intractable problems. To recuperate Barad’s challenge to contest assumptive distinctions while avoiding her epistemological problems, I offer some parting reflections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To acknowledge this turn does not require acceding to the reification of ‘social causes’ or ‘social facts’.

  2. While Barad may talk about more physical conceptions of ‘matter’ and the ‘nonhuman’ than others like Pickering, Latour, and Rouse, her intent is to generalize her findings into an account of material-discursive practices that cut across particular conceptions of ‘matter’ and even differences in methodologies (Barad 2007: 146–150). Her project against humanism is the same thread of thought as those theorists above.

  3. Ironically, Trevor Pinch (2011) criticizes Barad for her apparent disinterest in the social and historical contexts that have infused physicists’ thought and the field of science studies.

  4. I use the term ‘anti-humanism’ differently than Barad. Barad says that she is not ‘anti-humanist’ in the way that structuralists and post-structuralists make “human bodies and subjectivities … the effects of human-based discursive practices” (2007: 171). She is not ‘anti-humanist’ in that manner because, according to her, that is still a form of humanism. In contrast, I use the term as against humanism in whatever form that makes the human the center of analysis.

  5. Schatzki (2002: 109–119) also advances that the material world cannot make itself intelligible without humans. He interprets Rouse (1996) as arguing that matter can render itself intelligible (like Barad), but Schatzki rejects that view endorsing what Rouse calls a dispensable ‘residual humanism,’ that intelligibility requires human thought and practice. Thus, what Rouse seeks to purge from epistemology, Schatzki finds it necessary. I argue the same.

References

  • Barad, K. (1996). Meeting the universe halfway: Realism and social constructivism without contradiction. In L. Nelson & J. Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 161–194). Boston, MA: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (2003). Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter comes to matter. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 28, 801–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (2007). Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the entanglement of matter and meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (2011). Erasers and erasures: Pinch’s unfortunate ‘uncertainty principle’. Social Studies of Science, 41(3), 443–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Folse, H. J. (1985). The philosophy of Niels Bohr: The framework of complementarity. New York, NY: North Holland Physics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hekman, S. (2010). The material of knowledge: Feminist disclosures. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hird, M. (2009). Feminist engagements with matter. Feminist Studies, 35, 329–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Concluding unscientific postscript to Philosophical fragments (Vol. 1) [H. Hong & E. Hong (Eds. & Trans.)]. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Kukla, R. (2008). Naturalizing objectivity. Perspectives on Science, 16, 285–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2007). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1946). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (1995). Objectivity and the double standard for feminist epistemologies. Synthese, 104, 351–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1995). The mangle of practice: Time, agency, and science. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinch, T. (2011). Karen Barad, quantum mechanics, and the paradox of mutual exclusivity. Social Studies of Science, 41(3), 431–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1977). Realism and Reason. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 50(6), 483–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (1996). Engaging science: How to understand its practices philosophically. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2002). Vampires: Social constructivism, realism, and other philosophical undead. History and Theory, 41, 60–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2003). How scientific practices matter: Reclaiming philosophical naturalism. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2004). Barad’s feminist naturalism. Hypatia, 19, 142–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, T. (2002). The site of the social: A philosophical account of the constitution of social life and change. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, T., Knorr Cetina, K., & von Savigny, E. (Eds.). (2001). The practice turn in contemporary theory. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanesini, A. (2010). Naturalism and normativity: Rorty and Barad. In M. Janack (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Richard Rorty (pp. 199–216). University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wehling, P. (2006). The situated materiality of scientific practices: Postconstructivism—A new theoretical perspective in science studies? Science, Technology & Innovation Studies, 1, 81–100.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Calvert-Minor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Calvert-Minor, C. Epistemological Misgivings of Karen Barad’s ‘Posthumanism’. Hum Stud 37, 123–137 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9285-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9285-x

Keywords

Navigation