Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Biodiversity? Yes, But What Kind? A Critical Reassessment in Light of a Challenge from Microbial Ecology

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

… Concepts, which have proved useful for ordering things, easily assume so great an authority over us, that we forget their terrestrial origin and accept them as unalterable facts. They then become labeled as ‘conceptual necessities’, ‘a priori situations’, etc. The road to scientific [and moral] progress is frequently blocked for long periods by such errors. It is therefore not just an idle game to exercise our ability to analyze familiar concepts, and to demonstrate the conditions on which their justification and usefulness depend, and the way in which these developed […]. In this way, they are deprived of their excessive authority.

Albert Einstein, 1916 Obituary for Mach.

Abstract

Biodiversity has become one of the most important conservation values that drive our ecological management and directly inform our environmental policy. This paper highlights the dangers of strategically appropriating concepts from ecological sciences and also of uncritically inserting them into conservation debates as unqualified normative landmarks. Here, I marshal evidence from a cutting-edge research program in microbial ecology, which shows that if species richness is our major normative target, then we are faced with extraordinary ethical implications. This example challenges our well-received beliefs about biodiversity and it invites us to critically rethink the nature of this concept so that a more robust understanding of biodiversity and of its role in conservation policy could emerge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lennox claims that the conceptual benefit of such concepts lies in their capacity to overcome both the relativist option, which relates values to specific forms of culture and history, and the reductionist option, which reduces some medical judgments to statistical judgments (statistical outriders in case of sick people). The concept of health can be both “based on an empirical biological foundation and be evaluative” (Lennox 1995, p. 499) at the same time. There is a sense in which certain features of life provide an objective validation for a certain class of value concepts.

  2. This approach has been labeled as the hybrid approach, which is a combination of naturalism and normativism (Ereshefsky 2009). Bryan Norton calls such concepts “bridge terms” since they link social values and public policy to scientific data and theory (2008, p. 369).

  3. In their seminal work, Method in Ecology: Strategies for Conservation, Kristin Shrader-Frechette and Earl D. McCoy provide a strong critique of two foundational concepts in ecology: stability and community (1993, pp. 11–67). Their argument led them to claim “there is no biological coherent notion of “community” robust enough to ground either contemporary scientific theory in community ecology or environmental ethics” (1996, p. 59), and any environmental ethic grounded on those concepts is destined to fail. Ecologists have also shown that natural systems are typically disturbed without a natural tendency toward mature and stable states (Reice 1994). This fact certainly has a direct impact on an ecocentric ethic. As Hettinger and Throop claim, “Leopold’s dictum […] seems all too vulnerable to the charge that we may be obligating ourselves to preserve something that frequently does not exist” (2008, p. 190). In similar vein, Jamieson shows that the notion of ecosystem health, which might be useful as a rhetorical tool, has little utility as a technical term in environmental policy precisely because “there is little agreement in what health consists in or how to bring it about” (1995, p. 342).

  4. See also recent work by Santana (2014) and a recent rebuttal by Burch-Brown and Archer (2017).

  5. This is certainly Bryan Norton’s approach in his critique of Nelson’s argument for ecosystem health (Nelson 1995). Norton shows that Nelson’s argument “commits us to ‘attributing’ value to nature” (Norton 1995, p. 325), and its error lies in a commitment to an implausible view, namely that “nature has a ‘good of its own’ in some metaphysically independent sense” (Norton 1995, pp. 325–326; see also Norton 1988).

  6. A broad notion of value that accounts either for the instrumental or intrinsic value nature (in our case of the Amazon rainforest) would be sufficient to set up our argument. I do not need to take sides on which framework [economic/instrumental (Randall 1986; Maclaurin and Sterelny 2008, ch. 8) vs. intrinsic value (Rolston 2001; Callicott 1997)] provides us the best justification for the normative source of such an ecosystem. I believe that a pluralistic (additive and not competitive) view regarding the normative source of biodiversity is preferable.

  7. As Donald Maier points out in his book (2012), this imperative combines two formal ethical models: a just so and an incremental model. The goal of a just-so model is “to conserve something close what biodiversity currently exists” (p. 142). The incremental model is based on a fundamental correlation between biodiversity and its value. “If biodiversity increases, its value also increases” (p. 132) In this paper, I challenge the incremental aspects of a biodiversity.

  8. By biological respectability, I understand a combination of factors working in concert. Biodiversity, which in part is meant to act as a “total picture” of the natural world (E.O. Wilson in Takacs 1996, p. 50), has to be a definable concept. Ecologists and conservation biologist should provide us with a definition for this term, even if the definition might not be totally uncontroversial. In addition, biodiversity has to be measurable, and, as a consequence, it has to be part of theories that can make testable predictions about various natural patterns and ecosystem functioning. Lastly, a hallmark for such respectability is whether biodiversity is part of common ecological knowledge and of extended ecological research programs (Lakatos 2013).

  9. For a recent view regarding rates of extinctions, see Pimm and Raven (2000).

  10. Some claim that there is no single measure of biodiversity or that no measure satisfies the conditions of adequacy ecological sciences have demanded for (see list, Sarkar 2007, p. 394). For more details, see Ricotta (2005) and with respect to the measurability debate, see Sarkar (2006) especially the Sect. 2 (Measures of Ecological Diversity).

  11. Gaston and Spicer points out a few of the limitations of this definition: problematic definition of species and different kinds of diversity (Gaston and Spicer 2004, pp. 14–16; see also Claridge et al. 1997). Maclaurin and Sterelny raise a similar concern when they note a ‘striking fact’, namely that “evolutionary theory has been home to a long and continuing debate about the nature of species, that resulted in a profusion of species concepts” (Maclaurin and Sterelny 2008, p. 28). In the second chapter of their book on biodiversity, “Species: A modest Proposal”, Maclaurin and Sterelny show how this difficulty can be overcome by appealing to a phenomenological notion of species (See, Ibid, pp. 31–41). For a critique of Maclaurin and Sterelny’s species proposal, see Morgan (2010).

  12. For example, we could genetically tailor organisms that gain higher tolerances and capacities for adaptation to specifically dramatic environments. The rapid development of synthetic biology, with the creation of the first synthetic bacterial genome (Gibson et al. 2010) invite us to consider such technological possibilities as part of our near future.

  13. Another eloquent example of the problem of “appropriate increase” appears in studies that have focused on exotic invasive species. Dov Sax and Steven Gaines have made a strong argument against one of the most common ecological principles: predation by exotic plants drives down local biodiversity. They have shown that, when the European settlers brought exotic species to New Zealand, the native plants did not become extinct, and this process of naturalization instead of reducing biodiversity, it has led to a positive change in net species richness. I will additionally develop this example in the next section, as a paradigmatic case of how to rethink critically the policy application of the concept of biodiversity.

  14. In this paper, I assume that the importance of microbial life for biodiversity is a widely accepted fact. Skeptics should review the work of Staley and Reysenbach (2001) and Van Der Heijden et al. (2008).

  15. The Bohannan team has also confirmed the results of Jesus et al. (2009). See also Petersen et al. (2019) for a meta-analysis looking at how bacterial communities respond to land use change across the tropics.

  16. Microbiologist Bonnie L Bassler famously writes, “you may think you’ve seen everything, but in fact, most of the world is invisible to us.” (Bassler 2012, p. 67) In terms of numbers, the microbial diversity (Bacteria and Archaea) absolutely exceeds the diversity of life at the level of Eukarya. Scientists have catalogued about ~ 1.2 million of eukaryotes species, and predicted about 8.7 millions (Mora et al. 2011), whereas by 2011, microbial biologists have catalogued ~ 2, 492, 653 species and have predicted over 100 millions different species (or types) of microbes (Dykhuizen 1998).

  17. A significant conclusion of this research is to point out the specific impact of such ecosystem conversion onto microbial diversity. “The specific response we observed—an increase in alpha biodiversity and a decrease in beta diversity following environmental change” (Rodrigues et al. 2013). As Bohannan claims, “species richness is one aspect of diversity—how many types you find when you sample. But another aspect is how similar they are across space. And so we started to change our story to thinking: If we look at other aspects of diversity, is it the same? Which led us to then ask: If you compare any two cores from the pasture or the forest, on average do they share more or less of the types of the microbes present? And what we found was that in the forest, any two cores share fewer types than in the pasture. In other words each core is more different—more diverse—in the forest than in the pasture” (Bohannan 2012).

  18. As Sarkar rightly notes, “the need for justification is especially critical if we believe that these concerns deserve our attention despite equally important, if not more important, concerns we should have for improvements of the material conditions of the lives of the underprivileged” (2005, p. 2).

  19. Maclaurin and Sterelny point out also the difficulty of properly conceptualizing and finding a solution to the units-and-differences problem (2008, 20).

  20. In a recent publication, Malaterre shows that given the significance of microbial life, in addition to the units-measures difficulty, the concept faces a lower limit difficulty and the extent to which it should include microbial entities (2013). For a recent attempt to produce a unifying theory of biodiversity, see Scheffer et al. (2018).

  21. Another interesting critique of Sarkar’s approach was raised by J. Koricheva and H. Siipi [along the same lines with DeLong (1996)]. “The attempts […] to narrow the scope of the concept of biodiversity, either spatially, temporally, or with respect to the number of elements included seem to be driven by the desire to restrict the definition to those aspects which can be assessed empirically (i.e. species richness in a given locality). This approach, however, confounds definition with application, and is partly to blame for the terminological confusion surrounding the concept of biodiversity” (2004, p. 30).

  22. Cardinale et al. have produced a recent meta-analysis (2011) where they take a more nuanced view concerning the biodiversity—ecosystem functioning debate. However, as Shavit and Griesemer (2009) show, the problem of locality is pervasive in ecology and renders the replication of biodiversity surveys particularly difficult.

  23. James Brown has shown that fish also follows a similar pattern. For more details see also, Brown and Sax (2004).

References

  • Aoki, I. (2003). Diversity-productivity-stability relationship in freshwater ecosystems: Whole-systemic view of all trophic levels. Ecological Research, 18, 397–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bassler, B. (2012). Microbes as menaces, mates & marvels. Daedalus, 141(3), 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beever, J., & Morar, N. (2017). Interconnectedness and interdependence: Challenges for public health ethics. American Journal of Bioethics, 17(9), 19–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohannan, B. (2012). Google this: The story of science, In: Cascade, Spring 2011. Available at http://cascade.uoregon.edu/spring2012/expert/expert-article/. Accessed 19 May 2018.

  • Bond, E. M., & Chase, J. M. (2002). Biodiversity and Ecosystem functioning at local and regional spatial scales. Ecological Letters, 5, 467–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, & Sax, (2004). An essay on some topics concerning invasive species. Austral Ecology, 29, 530–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burch-Brown, J., & Archer, A. (2017). In defense of biodiversity. Biology and Philosophy, 32, 969–997.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. B. (1997). Values and ethics in conservation. In G. K. Meffee & C. R. Caroll (Eds.), Principles of conservation biology (pp. 29–56). Sunderland: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. B., Crowder, L. B., & Mumford, K. (1999). Current normative concepts in conservation. Conservation Biology, 13, 22–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardinale, B. J., Ives, A. R., & Inchausti, P. (2004). Effects of species diversity on the primary productivity of ecosystems: extending our spatial and temporal scales of inference. Oikos, 104, 437–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardinale, B. J., et al. (2011). The functional role of producer diversity in ecosystems. American Journal of Botany, 98(3), 572–592

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardinale, B., et al. (2012). Biodiversity loss and its impact on humanity. Nature, 486, 59–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caumette, P., et al. (2015). Some historical elements of microbial ecology. In J.-C. Bertrand, et al. (Eds.), Environmental microbiology: Fundamentals and applications: Microbial ecology (pp. 9–24). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Claridge, M. F., Dawah, H. A., & Wilson, M. R. (Eds.). (1997). Species: The units of biodiversity. London: Chapman Hall Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M., Linquist, S., Grey, W., Griffiths, P., Odenbaugh, J., & Possingham, H. P. (2009). Philosophical issues in ecology: Recent trends and future directions. Ecology and Society, 14(2), 22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeLong, D. (1996). Defining biodiversity. Wildlife Society Bulletin, 24, 738–749.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirzo, R., & Raven, P. H. (2003). Global state of biodiversity and loss. Annual Review of Environment and Resources, 28, 137–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dykhuizen, D. (1998). Santa Rosalia: Why are there so many species of bacteria? Antonie van Leeuwenhoek, 73(1), 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1971). 1916 Obituary for Mach. In Born (Ed.), The born-Einstein letters (p. 159). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2009). Defining health and disease. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40, 221–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forest, F., Grenyer, R., Rouget, M., Davies, T. J., Cowling, R. M., Faith, D. P., et al. (2007). Preserving the evolutionary potential of floras in biodiversity hotspots. Nature, 445, 757–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaston, K. J. (Ed.). (1996). Biodiversity: A biology of numbers and difference. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaston, Kevin, & Spicer, John. (2004). Biodiversity: An introduction. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, D., et al. (2010). Creation of a bacterial cell controlled by a chemically synthesized genome. Science, 329(5987), 52–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, A., et al. (2016). Estimating local biodiversity change: a critique of papers claming no net loss of local diversity, Ecology, 97(8), 1949–1960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hettinger, N., & Throop, B. (2008). Refocusing ecocentrism. In L. Pojman & P. Pojman (Eds.), Environmental ethics (pp. 186–200). New York: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillebrand, H. (2004). On the generality of the latitudinal diversity gradient. American Scientist, 163(2), 192–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huston, M. A. (1997). Hidden treatments in ecological experiments: Re-evaluating the ecosystem function of biodiversity. Oecologia, 110, 449–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huston, M. A., et al. (2000). No consistent effect of plant diversity on productivity. Science, 289(5483), 1255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, Dale. (1995). Ecosystem health: Some preventive medicine. Environmental Values, 4(4), 333–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jesus E. D., et al. (2009). Changes in land use alter the structure of bacterial communities in Western Amazon soils. The ISME Journal 3(9), 1004–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Justus, J., & Sarkar, S. (2002). The principle of complementarity in the design of reserve networks to conserve biodiversity: a preliminary history, Journal of Biosciences, 27(4), 421–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koricheva, Julia, & Siipi, Helena. (2004). The phenomenon of biodiversity. In Marrku Oksanen & Juhani Pietarinen (Eds.), Philosophy and biodiversity (pp. 27–53). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, Imre. (2013). Science and pseudoscience. In M. Curd, J. Cover, & C. Pincock (Eds.), Philosophy of science (pp. 20–26). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. (1995). Health as an objective value. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 20, 499–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy, T. (2002). Biodiversity: Dismissing scientific process. Scientific American, 268(1), 69–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur, R. H. (1972). Geographical ecology. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity?. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Madsen, E. L. (2011). Microorganisms and their roles in fundamental biogeochemical cycles. Current Opinion in Biotechnology, 22, 456–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Donald. (2012). What’s so good about biodiversity?. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Malaterre, C. (2013). Microbial diversity and the “lower-limit” problem of biodiversity. Biology and Philosophy, 28(2), 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malhi, Y., et. al. (2008). Climate Change, Deforestation, and the Fate of the Amazon. Science, 319(5860), 169–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margules, C., & Sarkar, S. (2007). Systematic conservation planning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mittelbach, G. (2012). Community ecology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mora, C., et al. (2011). How many species are there on earth and in the ocean? PLOS. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morar, N., Toadvine, T., & Bohannan, B. (2015). Biodiversity at twenty-five years: Revolution Or red herring? Ethics, Policy, and Environment, 18(1), 16–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Gregory. (2010). Evaluating Maclaurin and Sterelny’s conception of biodiversity in cases of frequent, promiscuous lateral gene transfer. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 603–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naeem, S., & Li, S. (1997). Biodiversity enhances ecosystem reliability. Nature, 390, 507–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naeem, S., Thompson, L. J., Lawler, S. P., Lawton, J. H., & Woodfin, R. M. (1994). Declining biodiversity can alter the performance of ecosystems. Nature, 368, 734–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, James. (1995). Health and disease as thick concepts in ecosystemic contexts. Environmental Values, 4(4), 311–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nguyen, H., et al. (2012). Biodiversity–productivity relationships in small-scale mixed-species plantations using native species in Leyte province, Philippines. Forest Ecology and Management, 274, 81–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. G. (1988). Commodity amenity and morality: The limits of quantification in valuing biodiversity. In E. O. Wilson (Ed.), Biodiversity. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. G. (1995). Objectivity, intrinsicality, and sustainability. Environmental Values, 4(4), 323–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. G. (2008). Biodiversity: Its meaning and value. In S. Sarkar & A. Plutynski (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of biology. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, I., Meyer, K., & Bohannan, B. (2019). Consistent bacterial responses to land use change across the tropics. bioRxiv. https://doi.org/10.1101/600924.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pimm, S., & Raven, P. (2000). Extinction by numbers. Nature, 483, 843–845.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Randall, A. (1986). Human preferences, economics, and the preservation of species. In B. G. Norton (Ed.), The preservation of species: The value of biological diversity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reice, Seth. (1994). Nonequilibrium, determinants of biological community structure. American Scientist, 82, 424–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricotta, C. (2005). Through the jungle of biological diversity. Acta Biotheoretica, 53(1), 29–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodrigues, Jorge L. M., et al. (2013). Conversion of the Amazon rainforest to agriculture results in biotic homogenization of soil bacterial communities. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 110(3), 988–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H. (2001). Biodiversity. In Dale Jamieson (Ed.), A companion to environmental philosophy (pp. 402–415). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Santana, C. (2014). Save the planet: Eliminate biodiversity. Biology and Philosophy, 29, 761–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. (2002). Defining biodiversity; assessing biodiversity. The Monist, 85(1), 131–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. (2005). Biodiversity and environmental philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. (2006). Ecological diversity and biodiversity as concepts for conservation planning: Comments on Ricotta. Acta Biotheoretica, 54(2), 133–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, Sahotra. (2007). From ecological diversity to biodiversity. In M. Ruse & D. Hull (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to biodiversity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S., & Margules, C. (2002). Operationalizing biodiversity for conservation planning. Journal of Biosciences, 27, 299–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sax, D., & Gaines, S. (2008). Species invasion and extinction: The future of native biodiversity on island. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 105(1), 11490–11497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffer, M., et al. (2018). Toward a unifying theory of biodiversity. PNAS, 115(4), 639–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shavit, A., & Griesemer, J. (2009). There and back again, or the problem of locality in biodiversity surveys. Philosophy of Science, 76(3), 273–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1996). Individualism, holism, and environmental ethics. Ethics & The Environment, 1(1), 55–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. S., & McCoy, E. D. (1993). Method in ecology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singh, B., et al. (2010). Microorganisms and climate change: Terrestrial feedbacks and mitigation options. Nature Reviews Microbiology, 8, 779–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soares-Filho, B. S., et al. (2006). Modelling conservation in the Amazon basin. Nature, 440, 520–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Srivastava, Diane, & Vellend, Mark. (2005). Biodiversity-ecosystem function research: Is it relevant to conservation? Annual Review of Ecology Evolution and Systematics, 36, 267–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staley, J. T., & Reysenbach, A.-L. (2001). Biodiversity of microbial life: Foundation of earth’s biosphere. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takacs, D. (1996). The idea of biodiversity: Philosophies of paradise. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tangley, L. (1986). Biological diversity goes public. Biosciences, 36(11), 708–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tilman, D. (1996). Biodiversity: Population versus ecosystem stability. Ecology, 77, 350–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tilman, D., Knops, J., Wedin, D., & Reich, P. (2002). Plant diversity and composition: Effects on productivity and nutrient dynamics of experimental grasslands. In M. Loreau, S. Naeem, & P. Inchausti (Eds.), Biodiversity and ecosystem functioning: Synthesis and perspectives (pp. 21–35). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tilman, D., Wedin, D., & Knops, J. (1996). Productivity and sustainability influenced by biodiversity in grassland ecosystems. Nature, 379, 718–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Congress. (1987). Technologies to maintain biological diversity. Philadelphia: Office of Technology Assessment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Der Heijden, M. G. A., Bardgett, R. D., & Van Straalen, N. M. (2008). The unseen majority: soil microbes as drivers of plant diversity and productivity in terrestrial ecosystems. Ecology Letters, 11, 296–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vellend, M. (2017). The biodiversity conservation paradox. American Scientist, 105, 94–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vellend, M., et al. (2013). Global meta-analysis reveals no net change in local-scale plant biodiversity over time. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110, 19456–19459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O., & Peter, F. M. (Eds.). (1988). BioDiversity. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wislon, E. O. (2002). What is nature worth? (pp. 20–40). Winter: The Wilson Quarterly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woese, C. (1998). A manifesto for microbial genomics. Current Biology, 8(22), 781–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woese, C., & Fox, G. E. (1977). Phylogenetic structure of the prokaryotic domain: the primary kingdoms. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 4(11):5088-5090.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmer, Carl. (2008). Friendly invaders. New York: The New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank B. Bohannan, T. Toadvine, and J. Beever for thoughtful and encouraging comments on early drafts of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicolae Morar.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Morar, N. Biodiversity? Yes, But What Kind? A Critical Reassessment in Light of a Challenge from Microbial Ecology. J Agric Environ Ethics 32, 201–218 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09758-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09758-3

Keywords

Navigation