Skip to main content
Log in

Pathwise Duals of Monotone and Additive Markov Processes

  • Published:
Journal of Theoretical Probability Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper develops a systematic treatment of monotonicity-based pathwise dualities for Markov processes taking values in partially ordered sets. We show that every Markov process that takes values in a finite partially ordered set and whose generator can be represented in monotone maps has a pathwise dual process. In the special setting of attractive spin systems, this has been discovered earlier by Gray. We show that the dual simplifies a lot when the state space is a lattice (in the order-theoretic meaning of the word) and all monotone maps satisfy an additivity condition. This leads to a unified treatment of several well-known dualities, including Siegmund’s dual for processes with a totally ordered state space, duality of additive spin systems, and a duality due to Krone for the two-stage contact process, and allows for the construction of new dualities as well. We show that the well-known representation of additive spin systems in terms of open paths in a graphical representation can be generalized to additive Markov processes taking values in general lattices, but for the process and its dual to be representable on the same underlying space, we need to assume that the lattice is distributive. In the final section, we show how our results can be generalized from finite state spaces to interacting particle systems with finite local state spaces.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. More formally, we require that there exist four functions \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s,t}\), \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s-,t}\), \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s,t-}\), and \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s-,t-}\) such that \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s-,t}=\lim _{u\uparrow s}{{\mathbf {X}}}_{u,t}\) and \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s,t}=\lim _{u\downarrow s}{{\mathbf {X}}}_{u-,t}\), and likewise with t replaced by \(t-\), and with the roles of the first and second variable interchanged.

  2. The alternative is to take \({{\mathbf {Y}}}_{-u,(-t)-}(y)\) which is right-continuous but notationally cumbersome.

  3. The connection between pathwise duality and invariant subspaces exposed here has an analog for (non-pathwise) duality. In [24, Prop 2.2], it is shown that if ST are finite sets and \(\psi :S\times T\rightarrow {{\mathbb {R}}}\) is such that the functions \(\{\psi (\cdot ,y):y\in T\}\) are linearly independent, then a Markov process X with state space S has a dual w.r.t. to the duality function \(\psi \) if and only if the semigroup of X maps the convex hull of \(\{\psi (\cdot ,y):y\in T\}\) into itself.

  4. Theorem 9 shows that a process X has a pathwise dual w.r.t. to the duality function \(\phi \) from (28) if X is monotonically representable. This condition is also necessary: If a map m has a dual w.r.t. to \(\phi \), then \(m^{-1}\) maps decreasing sets into decreasing sets and hence, by Lemma 5, m is monotone.

  5. See formulas (10)–(12) of [12]. His notation for \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s,t}(x)\) is \(\xi (s,t,x)\).

  6. Gray does not state his definition entirely correctly. In his definition of minimality, he also includes, probably inadvertently, the condition that \({\tilde{\pi }}(s)=x\).

  7. Alternatively, one may consider the map \(x\mapsto \big (\{x\}^\uparrow \cap \varLambda \big )^{\mathrm{c}}\) where \(\varLambda \) is the set of meet-irreducible elements of S. As a result of Birkhoff’s representation theorem, one can prove that this map is onto, and as a result sets up an isomorphism between the lattices S and \({{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(\varLambda )\), if and only if S is distributive.

  8. Let S and T be partially ordered sets. If a map \(m:S\rightarrow T\) is monotone, then it is also monotone with respect to the reversed orders on S and T. In view of this and Lemma 5 (i), a map \(m:S\rightarrow T\) is monotone if and only if \(m^{-1}(A)\in {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{inc}}(S)\) for all \(A\in {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{inc}}(T)\).

References

  1. Alkemper, R., Hutzenthaler, M.: Graphical representation of some duality relations in stochastic population models. Electron. Commun. Probab. 12, 206–220 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Athreya, S.R., Swart, J.M.: Branching-coalescing particle systems. Probab. Theory Relat. Fields 131(3), 376–414 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Birkhoff, G.: Rings of sets. Duke Math. J. 3(3), 443–454 (1937)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Carinci, G., Giardinà, C., Giberti, C., Redig, F.: Dualities in population genetics: a fresh look with new dualities. Stoch. Process. Appl. 125(3), 941–969 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Cox, J.T., Roesler, U.: A duality relation for entrance and exit laws for Markov processes. Stoch. Process. Appl. 16, 141–156 (1984)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Clifford, P., Sudbury, A.: A sample path proof of the duality for stochastically monotone Markov processes. Ann. Probab. 13, 558–565 (1985)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Davey, B.A., Priestley, H.A.: Introduction to Lattices and Order, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2002)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Diaconis, P., Fill, J.A.: Strong stationary times via a new form of duality. Ann. Probab. 18(4), 1483–1522 (1990)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Ethier, S.N., Kurtz, T.G.: Markov Processes: Characterization and Convergence. Wiley, London (1986)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Fill, J.A., Machida, M.: Stochastic monotonicity and realizable monotonicity. Ann. Probab. 29(2), 938–978 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Giardinà, C., Kurchan, J., Redig, F., Vafayi, K.: Duality and hidden symmetries in interacting particle systems. J. Stat. Phys. 135(1), 25–55 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Gray, L.: Duality for general attractive spin systems with applications in one dimension. Ann. Probab. 14(2), 371–396 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Griffeath, D.: Additive and Cancellative Interacting Particle Systems. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 724. Springer, Berlin (1979)

  14. Harris, T.E.: Additive set-valued Markov processes and graphical methods. Ann. Probab. 6, 355–378 (1978)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Huillet, T., Martinez, S.: Duality and intertwining for discrete Markov kernels: relations and examples. Adv. Appl. Probab. 43(2), 437–460 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Jansen, S., Kurt, N.: On the notion(s) of duality for Markov processes. Probab. Surv. 11, 59–120 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Kamae, T., Krengel, U., O’Brien, G.L.: Stochastic inequalities on partially ordered spaces. Ann. Probab. 5(6), 899–912 (1977)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Kolokoltsov, V.: Stochastic monotonicity and duality for one-dimensional Markov processes. Math. Notes 89(5), 652–660 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Kolokoltsov, V., Lee, R.X.: Stochastic duality of Markov processes: a study via generators. Stoch. Anal. Appl. 31, 992–1023 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Krone, S.: The two-stage contact process. Ann. Appl. Probab. 9(2), 331–351 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Lee, R.X.: The existence and characterisation of duality of Markov processes in the Euclidean space. Ph.D. thesis, University of Warwick. http://go.warwick.ac.uk/wrap/61991 (2013)

  22. Liggett, T.M.: Interacting Particle Systems. Springer, New York (1985)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Levin, D.A., Peres, Y., Wilmer, E.L.: Markov Chains and Mixing Times. AMS, Providence (2009)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Möhle, M.: Duality and cones of Markov processes and their semigroups. Markov Process. Relat. Fields 19(1), 149–162 (2013)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Neuhauser, C.: A long range sexual reproduction process. Stoch. Process. Appl. 53, 193–220 (1994)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Noble, C.: Equilibrium behavior of the sexual reproduction process with rapid diffusion. Ann. Probab. 20(2), 724–745 (1992)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Ross, D.A.: A coherence theorem for ordered families of probability measures on a partially ordered space. Unpublished manuscript (1993)

  28. Siegmund, D.: The equivalence of absorbing and reflecting barrier problems for stochastically monotone Markov processes. Ann. Probab. 4(6), 914–924 (1976)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Sudbury, A., Lloyd, P.: Quantum operators in classical probability theory. II: the concept of duality in interacting particle systems. Ann. Probab. 23(4), 1816–1830 (1995)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Sudbury, A., Lloyd, P.: Quantum operators in classical probability theory. IV: quasi-duality and thinnings of interacting particle systems. Ann. Probab. 25(1), 96–114 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Sturm, A., Swart, J.M.: A particle system with cooperative branching and coalescence. Ann. Appl. Probab. 25(3), 1616–1649 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Sturm, A., Swart, J.M.: Monotone and additive Markov process duality. Preprint. arXiv:1510.06284v1 (2015)

  33. Sudbury, A.: Dual families of interacting particle systems on graphs. J. Theor. Probab. 13(3), 695–716 (2000)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Swart, J.M.: Duals and thinnings of some relatives of the contact process. Preprint (18 pages). arXiv:math.PR/0604335

  35. Swart, J.M.: Duals and thinnings of some relatives of the contact process. In: Hukov, M., Janura, M. (eds.) Prague Stochastics 2006, pp. 203–214. Matfyzpress, Prague (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Swart, J.M.: Interacting Particle Systems. Lecture Notes. http://staff.utia.cas.cz/swart/tea_index.html (2016)

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Fero Matúš and June Huh for useful discussions, and László Csirmaz for help with the proof of Lemma 15. We also thank two anonymous referees for a careful reading of the manuscript and some helpful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anja Sturm.

Additional information

Work sponsored by GAČR Grant P201/12/2613 and by DFG priority programme 1590 Grant STU527/1-1.

Appendices

Appendix 1: A Bit of Lattice Theory

In this appendix, we collect some elementary properties of partially ordered sets and lattices that are used in the paper.

Let S be a any set. Recall that a relation \(\le \) on S is called a partial order if it satisfies the axioms

  1. (i)

    \(x\le x\) \((x\in S)\).

  2. (ii)

    \(x\le y\) and \(y\le x\) implies \(x=y\) \((x,y\in S)\).

  3. (iii)

    \(x\le y\le z\) implies \(x\le z\) \((x,y\in S)\).

A partially ordered set (also called poset) is a set with a partial order defined on it. A total order is a partial order such that, moreover,

  1. (iv)

    \(x\le y\) or \(y\le x\) (or both) \((x,y\in S)\).

Increasing and decreasing sets and the notation \(A^\uparrow \) and \(A^\downarrow \) have already been defined in Sect. 2.3.

By definition, a minimal element of a set \(A\subset S\) is an \(x\in A\) such that \(\{y\in A:y\le x\}=\{x\}\). Maximal elements are minimal elements for the reversed order. The following simple observation is well-known.

Lemma 34

(Maximal elements) Let S be a partially ordered set and let \(A\subset S\) be finite. Then, for every \(x\in A\) there exists a maximal element \(y\in A\) such that \(y\ge x\).

Proof

Either x is a maximal element or there exists some \(x^{\prime }\in A\), \(x^{\prime }\ne x\), such that \(x^{\prime }\ge x\). Continuing this process, using the finiteness of A, we arrive after a finite number of steps at a maximal element. \(\square \)

In particular, Lemma 34 shows that every nonempty finite \(A\subset S\) has a maximal element. Applying this to the reversed order, we see that A also contains a minimal element.

Let S be a partially ordered set and \(A\subset S\). An upper bound of A is an element \(x\in S\) such that \(y\le x\) for all \(y\in A\). Note that in general x does not have to be an element of A. If there exists an element \(x\in A\) that is an upper bound of A, then such an element is necessarily unique. (Indeed, imagine that \(x^{\prime }\in A\) is also an upper bound for A, then \(x^{\prime }\le x\) and \(x\le x^{\prime }\).)

If A is decreasing and there exists an element \(x\in A\) that is an upper bound of A, then \(A=\{x\}^\downarrow \). Indeed, the fact that x is an upper bound means that \(A\subset \{x\}^\downarrow \) while by the facts that \(x\in A\) and A is decreasing, we have \(A\supset \{x\}^\downarrow \). A least upper bound of A is an element \(x\in S\) that is an upper bound of A and that satisfies \(x\le x^{\prime }\) for any (other) upper bound \(x^{\prime }\) of A. Note that \(\bigcap _{x\in A}\{x\}^\uparrow \) is the set of all upper bounds of A, which is an increasing set. Thus, a least upper bound of A is an element \(x\in \bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow \) that is a lower bound of \(\bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow \). By our earlier remarks, such an element is unique. Also, since \(\bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow \) is an increasing set, if there exists an element \(x\in \bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow \) that is a lower bound of \(\bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow \), then \(\bigcap _{x^{\prime }\in A}\{x^{\prime }\}^\uparrow =\{x\}^\uparrow \).

A partially ordered set S is a join-semilattice if and only if for each \(y,z\in S\), the set \(\{y,z\}\) has a least upper bound. Equivalently, this says that there exists an element \(x\in \{y\}^\uparrow \cap \{z\}^\uparrow \) that is a lower bound of \(\{y\}^\uparrow \cap \{z\}^\uparrow \). By our earlier remarks, such an element is unique and one must in fact have \(\{y\}^\uparrow \cap \{z\}^\uparrow =\{x\}^\uparrow \). We denote this unique element by \(x=:y\vee z\) and call it the supremum or join of x and y. Note that this (more traditional) definition of suprema and join-semilattices is equivalent to the definition in (19). Infima and meet-semilattices are defined in the same way, but with respect to the reversed order.

Each finite join-semilattice S is clearly bounded from above, since \(\bigvee _{x\in S}x\) is an upper bound; similarly finite meet-semilattices are bounded from below.

As already mentioned in Sect. 2.3, if S is a partially ordered set, then a nonempty increasing set \(A\subset S\) such that for every \(x,y\in A\) there exists a \(z\in A\) with \(z\le x,y\) is called a filter and a nonempty decreasing set A such that for every \(x,y\in A\) there exists a \(z\in A\) with \(x,y\le z\) is called an ideal.

The following lemma characterizes ideals in join-semilattices. An analog statement holds for filters. In a lattice-theoretic setting, this lemma is often taken as the definition of an ideal.

Lemma 35

(Ideals in join-semilattices) Let S be a join-semilattice and let \(A\subset S\). Then A is an ideal if and only if A is nonempty, decreasing, and \(x,y\in A\) imply \(x\vee y\) in A.

Proof

Let A be nonempty and decreasing. If \(x,y\in A\) imply \(x\vee y\) in A, then for every \(x,y\in A\) there is an element of A, namely \(x\vee y\), such that \(x\vee y\ge x,y\), showing that A is an ideal. Conversely, if A is an ideal, then for every \(x,y\in A\) there is an element \(z\in A\) such that \(z\ge x,y\) and hence \(z\ge x\vee y\), which by the fact that A is decreasing proves that \(x\vee y\in A\). \(\square \)

As already mentioned in Sect. 2.3, a principal filter is a filter that contains a minimal element and a principal ideal is an ideal that contains a maximal element. We state the following facts for ideals only; applying them to the reversed order yields analog statements for filters.

Lemma 36

(Principal ideals) Let S be a partially ordered set and let \(A\subset S\). Then:

  1. 1.

    If A is an ideal, then A contains at most one maximal element.

  2. 2.

    A is a principal ideal if and only if there exists some \(z\in S\) such that \(A=\{z\}^\downarrow \).

If A is moreover finite, then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (i)

    A is a principal ideal.

  2. (ii)

    A is an ideal.

  3. (iii)

    A is decreasing and contains a unique maximal element.

Proof

1. If A is an ideal and \(x,y\in A\) are maximal, then there exists some \(z\in A\) such that \(z\ge x,y\) and hence \(x=z=y\) by the definition of maximality.

2. Let A be a principal ideal with maximal element z. Then \(\{z\}^\downarrow \subset A\) by the fact that A is decreasing. The inclusion \(\{z\}^\downarrow \supset A\) follows by observing that if \(x\in A\), then by the definition of an ideal there exists some \(y\in A\) with \(y\le x,z\), and hence \(y=z\) by the maximality of z, so \(x\le y=z\). Conversely, it is straightforward to check that each set of the form \(\{z\}^\downarrow \) is a principal ideal.

The implications (i)\(\Rightarrow \)(ii) and (i)\(\Rightarrow \)(iii) are trivial. Assume that \(A\subset S\) is finite. Then (ii)\(\Rightarrow \)(i) by Lemma 34. We claim that moreover (iii)\(\Rightarrow \)(i). Let z be the unique maximal element of A. By 2, it suffices to prove that \(A=\{z\}^\downarrow \). Since A is decreasing, we have \(\{z\}^\downarrow \subset A\). To prove the other inclusion, we observe that for any \(x\in A\), by Lemma 34, there exists a maximal element \(y\in A\) such that \(y\ge x\). By assumption, z is the unique maximal element of A, so \(y=z\) and hence \(x\le z\), proving that \(x\in \{z\}^\downarrow \).

\(\square \)

Appendix 2: List of Notation

  • \(\subset \) used in the meaning of \(\subseteq \) throughout the paper.

  • 0, 1 general notation for the lower and upper bound of a partially ordered set [as defined below (19)].

  • \(\langle x,y\rangle :=1_{\textstyle \{x\le y^{\prime }\}}, x\in S,\ y\in S^{\prime }\) [see (23)].

  • \(\leadsto \) indicates the existence of an open path in a percolation substructure (see Sect. 2.6).

  • \(\vee ,\wedge \) supremum, infimum [see (19)].

  • \(A^\uparrow :=\{x\in S:x\ge y \text{ for } \text{ some } y\in A\}\supset A\).

  • \(A^\downarrow :=\{x\in S:x\le y \text{ for } \text{ some } y\in A\}\supset A\).

  • \(A_{\mathrm{max}},A_{\mathrm{min}}\) set of maximal, resp. minimal elements of A [see (29)].

  • \({{\mathcal {F}}}(S,T)\) space of all functions \(f:S\rightarrow T\).

  • \({{\mathcal {F}}}_{\mathrm{mon}}(S,T)\) space of all monotone maps \(m:S\rightarrow T\) [see (20)].

  • \({{\mathcal {G}}}\) set of maps used in the random mapping representation of a generator (see Sect. 2.2).

  • GH Markov process generator and dual generator [see (10) and (13)].

  • \(H_\dagger , H_*, H_\circ , H_\bullet \) dual generators [see (34)].

  • \({{\mathcal {K}}}(S,T)\) space of all probability kernels from S to T.

  • \(P_t\) transition probabilities (see Sect. 2.1).

  • \({{\mathcal {P}}}(S):=\{A:A\subset S\}\) set of all subsets of S.

  • \(\displaystyle {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{inc}}(S),\displaystyle {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(S)\) increasing, decreasing subsets of S [see (18)].

  • \(\displaystyle {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{!inc}}(S),\displaystyle {{\mathcal {P}}}_{\mathrm{!dec}}(S)\) principal filters, ideals of S [see (18)].

  • ST state spaces, mostly endowed with a partial order \(\le .\)

  • \(S^{\prime }\) dual of the partially ordered space S [see (22)].

  • \(X_t,Y_t\) Markov process and dual Markov process (see Sect. 2.1).

  • \({{\mathbf {X}}}_{s,t},{{\mathbf {Y}}}_{s,t}\) stochastic flows associated with Markov processes XY (see Sect. 2.1).

  • \(m:S\rightarrow S\) and \({\hat{m}}:T\rightarrow T\) map and dual map with respect to \(\psi \) [see (12)].

  • \(m^{\prime }\) dual map associated with an additive map m (see Lemma 6).

  • \(m^\dagger , m^*, m^\circ , m^\bullet \) dual maps associated with a monotone map m [see (30) and (36)].

  • \(x^{\mathrm{c}}\) complement of a set x.

  • \(x^{\prime },y^{\prime }\) elements of the dual space \(S^{\prime }\) associated with \(x,y\in S\) [see (22)].

  • \(\Delta ,\Delta _{s,t}\) Poisson point sets used in the graphical representation of a Markov process (see Sect. 2.2).

  • \(\varLambda \) a finite set (in Sects. 1234) or a countable set (in Sect. 5).

  • \(\phi , {\tilde{\phi }}:\) duality functions [see (28) and (35)].

  • \(\psi :S\times T\rightarrow {{\mathbb {R}}}\) duality function [see (2) and (4)].

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sturm, A., Swart, J.M. Pathwise Duals of Monotone and Additive Markov Processes. J Theor Probab 31, 932–983 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10959-016-0721-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10959-016-0721-5

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification (2010)

Navigation