Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Fragility, uncertainty, and healthcare

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Medicine seeks to overcome one of the most fundamental fragilities of being human, the fragility of good health. No matter how robust our current state of health, we are inevitably susceptible to future illness and disease, while current disease serves to remind us of various frailties inherent in the human condition. This article examines the relationship between fragility and uncertainty with regard to health, and argues that there are reasons to accept rather than deny at least some forms of uncertainty. In situations of current ill health, both patients and doctors seek to manage this fragility through diagnoses that explain suffering and provide some certainty about prognosis as well as treatment. However, both diagnosis and prognosis are inevitably uncertain to some degree, leading to questions about how much uncertainty health professionals should disclose, and how to manage when diagnosis is elusive, leaving patients in uncertainty. We argue that patients can benefit when they are able to acknowledge, and appropriately accept, some uncertainty. Healthy people may seek to protect the fragility of their good health by undertaking preventative measures including various tests and screenings. However, these attempts to secure oneself against the onset of biological fragility can cause harm by creating rather than eliminating uncertainty. Finally, we argue that there are good reasons for accepting the fragility of health, along with the associated uncertainties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The uncertainty of the patients about their health and the meaning of their symptoms may be compounded by responses to MUS by practitioners, such as hostility, frustration, and feelings of impotence [10]. These are qualitatively different to responses by practitioners to ‘regular’ medical uncertainty, as the absence of a diagnosis may lead the practitioner to question their own competence, as well as giving them feelings of failure in the face of patients’ ongoing suffering.

  2. Later in the article, we detail some of the ways in which tests may provide unreliable results, including mistakes, false negatives and false positives, and overdiagnosis; here, we focus on general uncertainty in healthcare regarding prognosis.

  3. See Renée Fox (1957) cited in [11, p. 5]; see also [12].

  4. We thank one of the editors for pointing out this distinction.

  5. This includes a growing literature on the mechanisms that doctors use to deal with uncertainty, such as denial, the seeking of specific and narrow diagnoses, the use of black humour, avoiding areas of medical practice where uncertainty is more prevalent (such as general practice, geriatrics, psychiatry), and relying on heuristics, which may be more or less biased [14].

  6. Avoiding the disclosure of uncertainty may also lead to self-deception about a doctor’s own competence or erode her capacity to recognise her limitations, with a detrimental effect on her expertise. We do not have space to explore this point further, but thank one of the editors for drawing it to our attention.

  7. The small interview study by Kathryn Ehrich et al. [17] suggests that in the context of novel procedures, patients accepted clinicians’ uncertainty and appreciated clear explanations of risk.

  8. In what follows, we do not intend to provide a comprehensive account of the ethical challenges of screening (see, e.g., [19, 20]). Rather we aim to explore potential uncertainty and vulnerability associated with at least some instances of screening.

  9. Current approaches to screening date back to the influential work of James Wilson and Gunner Jungner [21] whose 1968 principles for screening focus on the importance of screening being able to identify the early pre-symptomatic phases of significant diseases for which acceptable and effective treatment exists.

  10. For example, the NHS recommends the following routine screening for adults aged 30-64 years: cervical, breast, bowel, and prostate cancer, blood pressure, cholesterol, anaemia, thyroid, respiratory, heart, bone, kidney, and glaucoma [23].

  11. Here, we are thinking of the technical staff collecting specimens and performing analyses, as well as the doctors interpreting and reporting on the results, and other health professionals involved in diagnosis and treatment.

  12. We do not wish to imply that screening, for at least some diseases, is generally non-beneficial. Our concern is with the effects of screening on uncertainty and vulnerability, particularly where screening leads to false negatives, false positives, and overdiagnosis.

  13. Here, we discuss only overdiagnosis arising in the course of screening. There are other ways that overdiagnosis occurs, including in the context of patients presenting with symptoms. A full discussion of these matters is beyond the scope of this article; see, e.g., [27, 28].

  14. The leaflet states that of one hundred women screened, four may need more tests, one of whom is likely to have cancer. Of those diagnosed with invasive cancer, one woman will have her life saved by screening while another three will be overdiagnosed with and treated for a cancer that would never have become life threatening [33].

  15. We recognize that socio-economic factors significantly influence health status, such that the chances of suffering ill health are not equally distributed in populations. Nonetheless, even the most well off are not immune from ill health.

  16. Martha Fineman makes similar points in relation to vulnerability which she takes to be ‘a universal, inevitable, enduring aspect of the human condition, that must be at the heart of our concept of social and state responsibility’ [35, p. 166].

References

  1. Gawande, A. 2002. Complications: A surgeon’s notes on an imperfect science. New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Mackenzie, C., W. Rogers, and S. Dodds. 2014. Introduction: What is vulnerability and why does it matter for moral theory? In Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy, ed. C. Mackenzie, W. Rogers, and S. Dodds, 1–28. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Waymark, M.H. 2009. Yearning for certainty and the critique of medicine as “science”. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 30: 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Jutel, A. 2013. When pigs could ply: Influenza and the elusive nature of diagnosis. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 56(4): 513–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Wasfy, J.H. 2006. Learning about clinical uncertainty. Academic Medicine 81(12): 1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Undeland, M., and K. Malterud. 2007. The fibromyalgia diagnosis: Hardly helpful for patients? Scandinavian Journal for Primary Health Care 25: 250–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Nettleton, S., L. O’Malley, I. Watt, and P. Duffey. 2006. Enigmatic illness: Narrative of patients who live with medically unexplained symptoms. Social Theory and Health 2: 47–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Nettleton, S. 2004. ‘I just want permission to be ill’: Towards a sociology of medically unexplained symptoms. Social Science and Medicine 62: 1167–1178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Velleman, J.D. 2005. The self as narrator. In Self to self, ed. J.D. Velleman, 203–223. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Olde Hartman, T.C., L.J. Hassink-Franke, P.L. Lucassen, K.P. Van Spaendonck, and C. Van Weel. 2009. Explanation and relations: How do general practitioners deal with patients with persistent medically unexplained symptoms: A focus group study. BMC Family Practice 10: 68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Fox, R. 1980. The evolution of medical uncertainty. Milbank Memorial Fund Quarterly 58: 1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Fox, R. 2000. Medical uncertainty revisited. In The handbook of social studies in health and medicine, ed. G.L. Abrecht, R. Fitzpatrick, and S.C. Scrimshaw, 409–426. London: Sage.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Beresford, E.B. 1991. Uncertainty and the shaping of medical decisions. Hastings Centre Report 21(4): 6–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Hall, K.H. 2002. Reviewing intuitive decision-making and uncertainty: The implications for medical education. Medical Education 36: 216–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Seely, A.J.E. 2013. Embracing the certainty of uncertainty: Implications for health care and research. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 56(1): 65–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Parascandola, M., J.S. Hawkins, and M. Danis. 2002. Patient autonomy and the challenge of clinical uncertainty. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12(3): 245–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Ehrich, K., L. Cowie, and J. Sandall. 2015. Expect the unexpected: Patients’ and families’ expectations and experiences of new clinical procedures. Health Expectations 18(5): 918–928.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Katz, J. 1984. The silent world of doctor and patient. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Shickle, D., and R. Chadwick. 1994. The ethics of screening: Is ‘screeningitis’ an incurable disease? Journal of Medical Ethics 20: 12–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Ewart, R.M. 2000. Primum non nocere and the quality of evidence: Rethinking the ethics of screening. Journal of the American Board of Family Practice 13(3): 188–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Wilson, J.M.G., and G. Jungner. 1968. Principles and practice of screening for disease. Geneva: World Health Organization. http://www.who.int/bulletin/volumes/86/4/07-050112/en/. Accessed April 9, 2015.

  22. Crawford, R. 2004. Risk ritual and the management of control and anxiety in medical culture. Health 8(4): 505–528.

    Google Scholar 

  23. National Health Service. 2014. Health checks for ages 30 to 64. http://www.nhs.uk/livewell/screening/pages/checks30to64.aspx. Accessed April 8, 2015.

  24. Altman, D.G., and J.M. Bland. 1994. Statistics notes: Diagnostic tests 1: Sensitivity and specificity. BMJ 308: 1552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Tosteson, A.N.A., D.G. Fryback, C.S. Hammond, et al. 2014. Consequences of false-positive screening mammograms. JAMA Internal Medicine 174(6): 954–961.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Brodersen, J., and V.D. Siersma. 2013. Long-term psychosocial consequences of false-positive screening mammography. Annals of Family Medicine 11: 106–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Moyhihan, R., J. Doust, and D. Henry. 2012. Preventing overdiagnosis: How to stop harming the healthy. BMJ 344: e3502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Carter, S., W.A. Rogers, I. Heath, C. Degeling, J. Doust, and A. Barratt. 2015. The challenge of overdiagnosis begins with its definition. BMJ 350: h869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Welch, H.G., and W.C. Black. 2010. Overdiagnosis in cancer. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 102: 605–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Barratt, A. 2015. Overdiagnosis in mammography screening: A 45 year journey from shadowy idea to acknowledged reality. BMJ 350: h867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Entwistle, V.A., S.M. Carter, L. Trevena, K. Flitcroft, L. Irwig, K. McCaffrey, and G. Salkeld. 2008. Communicating about screening. BMJ 337(7673): 789–791.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Independent UK Panel on Breast Cancer Screening. 2012. The benefits and harms of breast cancer screening: an independent review. Lancet 380: 1778–1786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. National Health Service. 2013. NHS breast screening: Helping you decide. http://www.cancerscreening.nhs.uk/breastscreen/publications/ia-02.html. Accessed April 8, 2015.

  34. Hersch, J., A. Barratt, J. Jansen, et al. 2015. Use of a decision aid including information on overdetection to support informed choice about breast cancer screening: A randomised controlled trial. Lancet 385(9978): 1642–1652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Fineman, M.A. 2008. The vulnerable subject: Anchoring equality in the human condition. Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 20(1): 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank the editors for helpful comments on an earlier draft.

Funding

This study was funded by ARC Future Fellowship grant 130100346 (funding Rogers) and a Macquarie University Future Fellowship start up grant (funding Walker).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wendy A. Rogers.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflicts of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rogers, W.A., Walker, M.J. Fragility, uncertainty, and healthcare. Theor Med Bioeth 37, 71–83 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-016-9350-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-016-9350-3

Keywords

Navigation