Skip to main content
Log in

Incentivized goodness

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It will be argued that humans have a rational self-interest in voluntarily opting to subject themselves to moral bioenhancement. This interest is based on the fact that goodness appears to be conducive to happiness. Those who understand that will be more inclined to opt for safe and effective moral bioenhancement technologies that have the potential to augment our motivation to become better. The more people decide to follow this path, the likelier it is that states will adopt suitable policies that incentivize moral bioenhancement. Hence, goodness, happiness and state incentivized moral bioenhancement can operate in a circularly supportive fashion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In some of their later writings, Persson and Savulescu do not take a clear stance on whether MBE ought to become mandatory (e.g., Persson and Savulescu 2012). Still, they have never distanced themselves from their initial view that MBE ought to be made compulsory to all. Ostensibly, compulsory moral enhancement is required to avoid UH. However, given the value of freedom, autonomy, and for obvious political reasons, it would clearly be better to find another way to promote moral enhancement that does not require paternalistic measures. In this paper, I defend an alternative conception of implementing an MBE program that would, I submit, have just that effect.

  2. “Practical” is used here as an antonym of “theoretical”. The meaning of “practically superfluous” comes close to “functionally superfluous”. It denotes something that is inoperative.

  3. For a reply Persson and Savulescu gave to this article, see Persson and Savulescu (2014).

  4. Conversely, voluntary MBE leaves our moral reflection intact - precisely because it is voluntary. As long as we have a functioning reasoning capacity and will that are capable of determining what is morally right and wrong, as well as making us act in line with our judgments on this, our moral reflection remains uncompromised.

  5. One version of the trolley thought experiment is the following. A runaway trolley is about to kill five people who lie tied up on its track, unable to move. You can help. All you have to do is pull a hand lever to switch tracks, saving the five people. But there is a problem. Someone stands on the sidetrack unto which you can divert the trolley. There is no time to warn him. Hence, by pulling the hand lever and guiding the trolley to safety you will save five people, but at the same time have an active role in killing one person. A variety of complex moral issues arise when we think about which action is the morally justified one to take. A random enhancement of empathy, especially if it results in increased empathy for the person on the sidetrack, will not be of any help in guiding us to the morally right action in this thought experiment. On the other hand, moral reflection might be helpful.

  6. Happiness is understood here not as Ancient Greek eudaimonia (good life) but refers to a “thinner” psychological conception denoting a mental state of wellbeing.

  7. Although it might be argued that we are more likely to be taken advantage of if we are good, that line of reasoning is just an intuition. Undoubtedly, certain people will on certain occasions be inclined to take advantage of us. But others will not. It is difficult to generalize the notion that we will be more prone to be taken advantage of if we are good. One of the remedies against advantage takers is cognitive competency. Cognitive enhancement contributes therefore to moral enhancement. But it is not enough because we frequently do not act as we believe we ought to. Consequently, moral enhancement is something humans are also in need of.

  8. It is also possible to argue that VMBE at a collective level might operate as follows: some people would voluntarily opt for MBE, this would have an impact on others, and the “snowball effect” would lead to ever more people pursuing ever more dramatic forms of enhancement. It would be a kind of “slippery slope in reverse”. I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for this idea, although we agree that there is no evidence for the assumption that such a process would actually take place. However, the conception of VMBE does not need to assume that people will pursue ever more dramatic forms of enhancement. As it is not grounded on the objective of UH prevention, modest forms of moral enhancement contributing to an increase in human happiness and general wellbeing are also good enough.

References

  • Anik Lalin, Aknin Lara, B., I. Norton Michael, and W. Dunn Elizabeth. 2009. Feeling good about giving: The benefits (and costs) of self-interested charitable behavior. Harvard Business School Working Paper.

  • Baumeister, R. F., E. J. Masicampo, and C. N. DeWall. 2009. Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases agression and reduces helpfulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 35:260–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, T. 2008. Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (3): 228–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, Elizabeth W., B. Aknin Lara, and I. Norton Michael. 2008. Spending money on others promotes happiness. Science 319: 1687–1688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isen, Alice M., and F. Levin Paula. 1972. Effect of feeling good on helping: Cookies and kindness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21 (3): 384–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, H. C., R. D. Rogers, and R. E. Passingham. 2007. Manipulating the experienced onset of intention after action execution. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19: 81–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. 1986. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8: 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., C. A. Gleason, E. W. Wright, and D. K. Pearl. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106: 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I., and J. Savulescu. 2008. The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to enhance the moral character of humanity. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25: 162–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I., and J. Savulescu. 2012. Unfit for the future: The Need for Moral Enhancement. Oxford: Oxford Univerity Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, I., and J. Savulescu. 2014. Should moral bioenhancement be compulsory? Reply to Vojin Rakic. Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (4): 251–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakić, V. 2014. Voluntary moral enhancement and the survival-at-any-cost bias. Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (4): 246–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakić, V. 2015. We must create beings with moral standing superior to our own. Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics 24 (1): 58–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakić, V. 2017a. Moral bioenhancement and free will: Continuing the debate. Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics 26 (3): 384–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakić, V. 2017b. Compulsory administration of oxytocin does not result in genuine moral enhancement. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 20 (3): 291–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rigoni, D., S. Kühn, G. Gaudino, G. Sartori, and M. Brass. 2012b. Reducing self-control by weakening belief in free will. Consciousness and Cognition 21: 1482–1490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rigoni, D., S. Kühn, G. Sartori, and M. Brass. 2012a. Inducing disbelief in free will alters brain correlates of preconscious motor preparation: The brain minds whether we believe in free will or not. Psychological Science 22: 613–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheldon, K. M., and S. Lyubomirsky. 2004. Achieving sustainable new happiness: Prospects, practices, and prescriptions. In Positive psychology in practice, eds. A. Linley, and S. Joseph, 127–145. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohs, K. D., and J. W. Schooler. 2008. The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science 19: 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. 2003. The mind’s best trick: How we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 65–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vojin Rakić.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rakić, V. Incentivized goodness. Med Health Care and Philos 21, 303–309 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-017-9812-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-017-9812-z

Keywords

Navigation