Skip to main content
Log in

Multiple versus single immoral acts: an immoral person evokes more schadenfreude than an immoral action

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Motivation and Emotion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A small body of research has investigated the relationship between an immoral disposition and schadenfreude. Less work has investigated the relationship between immoral behavior and schadenfreude. The aim of the present study was to separate out dispositional and behavioral attributions by both manipulation and measurement and thereby to investigate individual pathways to schadenfreude. Participants (Study 1: N = 281, Study 2: N = 271) were presented with a scenario that described a single immoral act or multiple immoral acts. The latter resulted in greater attributions to dispositional immorality. Importantly, dispositional immorality attributions were found to predict schadenfreude, but behavioral immorality attributions had no independent effect on schadenfreude. The pathways to schadenfreude were partly mediated by condemning emotions directed at the person but not by condemning emotions directed at the behavior. These findings expand our understanding of the psychological processes that underlie schadenfreude.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There were more variables included in the study than reported here. These were responsibility and blame (as well as opinions on tax in Study 1). We have not included these variables as they are peripheral to our major research question and would detract from the flow in the current study.There were more variables included in the study than reported here. These were responsibility and blame (as well as opinions on tax in Study 1). We have not included these variables as they are peripheral to our major research question and would detract from the flow in the current study.

  2. In Study 1, we also measured dishonest and trustworthy (R) and in Study 2, we also measured deceitful and trustworthy (R) in addition to immorality. In each study, the overall pattern of findings was the same for the single item and combined item measures.

References

  • Alcock, J. E., Carment, D. W., & Sadava, S. W. (1991). A textbook of social psychology (2nd ed.). Scarborough, Ontario: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126(4), 556–574.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Ze'ev, A. (2002). Are envy, anger, and resentment moral emotions? Philosophical Explorations, 5, 148–154.

  • Ben-Ze’ev, A. (2014). The personal comparative concern in schadenfreude. In W. W. van Dijk & J. W. Ouwerkerk (Eds.), Schadenfreude: Understanding pleasure at the misfortune of others (pp. 77–90). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Berndsen, M., & Feather, N. T. (2016). Reflecting on schadenfreude: serious consequences of a misfortune for which one is not responsible diminish previously expressed schadenfreude; the role of immorality appraisals and moral emotions. Motivation and Emotion, 40, 895–913.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berndsen, M., Thomas, E. F., McGarty, C., Bliuc, A.-M., & Muntele Hendres, D. (2017a). Glorifying national identification increases schadenfreude about asylum seekers when they are a threat, not entitled to seek asylum, and blamed for their adversity. Comprehensive Results in Social Psychology, 2, 166–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berndsen, M., Tiggemann, M., & Chapman, S. (2017b). “It wasn’t your fault, but …..”: Schadenfreude about an undeserved misfortune. Motivation and Emotion, 4, 741–748.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H. (1972). Morality judgments: Tests for an averaging model. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 93, 35–42.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brambilla, M., & Leach, C. W. (2014). On the importance of being moral: The distinctive role of morality in social judgment. Social Cognition, 32, 397–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brambilla, M., & Riva, P. (2017). Predicting pleasure at others' misfortune: Morality trumps sociability and competence in driving deservingness and schadenfreude. Motivation and Emotion, 41, 243–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, M. B. (1999). The psychology of prejudice: In-group love and out-group hate. Journal of Social Issues, 55, 429–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakroff, A., Russell, P. S., Piazza, J., & Young, L. (2017). From impure to harmful: Asymmetric expectations about immoral agents. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 69, 201–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Combs, D. J. Y., Powell, C. A. J., Schurtz, D. R., & Smith, R. H. (2009). Politics, Schadenfreude, and in-group identification: The sometimes happy thing about a poor economy and death. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 4, 635–646.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. (1989). The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with the Wason selection task. Cognition, 31, 187–276.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dasborough, M., & Harvey, P. (2017). Schadenfreude: The (not so) secret joy of another’s misfortune. The Journal of Business Ethics, 141, 693–707.

    Google Scholar 

  • Effron, D. A., & Monin, B. (2010). Letting people off the hook: When do good deeds excuse transgressions? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 36, 1618–1634.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2015). Explaining social behavior: More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faul, F., Erdfelder, E., Lang, A.-G., & Buchner, A. (2007). G*Power 3: A flexible statistical power analysis program for the social, behavioral, and biomedical sciences. Behavior Research Methods, 39, 175–191.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Feather, N. T. (2008). Perceived legitimacy of a promotion decision in relation to deservingness, entitlement, and resentment in the context of affirmative action and performance. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 38, 1230–1254.

  • Feather, N. T. (2012). Tall poppies, deservingness and schadenfreude. The Psychologist, 25, 434–437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feather, N. T. (2014). Deservingness and schadenfreude. In W. W. van Dijk & J. W. Ouwerkerk (Eds.), Schadenfreude: Understanding pleasure at the misfortune of others (pp. 29–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feather, N. T., & McKee, I. R. (2014). Deservingness, liking relations, schadenfreude and discrete emotions in the context of the outcomes of plagiarism. Australian Journal of Psychology, 66, 18–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feather, N. T., & Sherman, R. (2002). Envy, resentment, schadenfreude, and sympathy: Reactions to deserved and undeserved achievement and subsequent failure. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 953–961.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S., et al. (2013). Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 55–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. T., & Malone, P. (1995). The correspondence bias. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 21–38.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). Moral character predominates in person perception and evaluation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 106, 148–168.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gutierrez, R., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2007). Anger, disgust, and presumption of harm as reactions to taboo-breaking behaviors. Emotion, 7, 853–868.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In R. J. Davidson, K. R. Scherer, & H. H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of affective sciences (pp. 852–870). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. In S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (5th ed., pp. 797–832). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hareli, S., & Parkinson, B. (2008). What’s social about social emotions? Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 38, 131–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hareli, S., & Weiner, B. (2002). Dislike and envy as antecedents of pleasure at another's misfortune. Motivation and Emotion, 26, 257–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooper, N., Erdogan, A., Keen, G., Lawton, K., & McHugh, L. (2015). Perspective taking reduces the fundamental attribution error. Journal of Contextual Behavioral Science, 4, 69–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, M. M., Dennett, D. C., & Adams, R. B. (2011). Inside jokes: Using humor to reverse-engineer the mind. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, F. (2017). Demonising drug users. https://www.victoria.ac.nz/capital-thinking/drug-users.

  • Jones, E. E., & Davis, K. E. (1965). From acts to dispositions: The attribution process in social psychology. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 219–266). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kassin, S. M., & Sukel, H. (1997). Coerced confessions and the jury: An experimental test of the “harmless error” rule. Law and Human Behaviour, 21, 27–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, H. H. (1967). Attribution theory in social psychology. In D. Levine (Ed.), Nebraska symposium on motivation (Vol. 15, pp. 129–238). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, H. H. (1971). Attribution in social interaction. In E. E. Jones, D. E. Kanouse, H. H. Kelley, R. E. Nisbett, S. Valins, & B. Weiner (Eds.), Attribution: Perceiving the causes of behavior (pp. 1–26). Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, H. H. (1973). The process of causal attribution. American Psychologist, 28, 107–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, N., & O’Brien, E. (2016). The tipping point of moral change: When do good and bad acts make good and bad actors? Social Cognition, 34, 149–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, R. B. (1998). Principles and practice of structural equation modeling. New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leach, C. W., Ellemers, N., & Barreto, M. (2007). Group virtue: The importance of morality (vs. competence and sociability) in the positive evaluation of in-groups. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 234–249.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Leach, C. W., & Spears, R. (2008). A vengefulness of the impotent’: The pain of in-group inferiority and schadenfreude toward successful out-groups. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 95, 1383–1396.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Li, X., McAllister, D. J., Ilies, R., & Gloor, J. L. (2019). Schadenfreude: A counternormative observer response to workplace mistreatment. Academy of Management Review, 44, 360–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippit, J.A. (1995). Humour and Superiority. Cogito 9.1, 54–69.

  • Marie, S. (2017) How to focus on the behavior and not the person during conflict management. https://peakconflictsolutions.com/index.php/2017/11/16/focus-behavior-not-person-conflict-management/

  • Martijn, C., Spears, R., van der Pligt, J., & Jakobs, E. (1992). Negativity and positivity effects in person perception and inference: Ability versus morality. European Journal of Social Psychology, 22, 453–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNamee, M. (2007). Nursing schadenfreude: The culpability of emotional construction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 10, 289–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1967 [1887]). On the genealogy of morals (translated by W. Kaufmann & R.J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House.

  • Monin, B., & Miller, D. (2001). Moral credentials and the expression of prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 33–43.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nabi, R. L. (2002). The theoretical versus the lay meaning of disgust: Implications for emotion research. Cognition and Emotion, 16, 695–703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olatunji, B. O., Puncochar, B., & Cox, R. (2016). Effects of experienced disgust on morally-relevant judgments. PLoS ONE, 11(8), e0160357.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Powell, C. A., & Smith, R. H. (2013). Schadenfreude caused by the exposure of hypocrisy in others. Self and Identity, 12, 413–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preacher, K. J., & Hayes, A. F. (2008). Asymptotic and resampling strategies for assessing and comparing indirect effects in multiple mediator models. Behavior Research Methods, 40, 879–891.

    Google Scholar 

  • Qiao, Y., Zhang, Z., & Jia, M. (2019). Their pain, our pleasure: How and when peer abusive supervision leads to third parties’ schadenfreude and work engagement. Journal of Business Ethics, 152, 133–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raney, A. A. (2004). Expanding disposition theory: Reconsidering character liking, moral evaluations, and enjoyment. Communication Theory, 14, 348–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeder, G. D., & Brewer, M. B. (1979). A schematic model of dispositional attribution in interpersonal perception. Psychological Review, 86, 61–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, S., Nelson, C., & Vivekananthan, P. S. (1968). A multi-dimensional approach to the structure of personality impressions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 9, 283–294.

  • Ross, L. (1977). The intuitive psychologist and his short-comings: Distortions in the attribution process. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 574–586.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, M. S., Lineberger, M., Correll, J., & Park, B. (2005). Emotions, attributions, and policy endorsements in response to the September 11th terrorist attacks. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 27, 249–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, K. (2012). “Bad’ kid or ‘bad’ behavior and how it shapes a child’s self-esteem. https://www.goodtherapy.org/blog/bad-kid-or-behavior-and-how-it-shapes-a-childs-self-esteem-0730125

  • Skowronski, J. J., & Carlston, D. E. (1987). Social judgment and social memory: The role of cue diagnosticity in negativity, positivity and extremity biases. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 689–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skowronski, J. J., & Carlston, D. E. (1989). Negativity and extremity biases in impression formation: A review of explanations. Psychological Bulletin, 105(131–1), 42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. H., & Kim, S. H. (2007). Comprehending envy. Psychological Bulletin, 133, 46–64.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stalder, D. R. (2019). Reducing conflict by avoiding attribution errors. https://www.actionteaching.org/award/attribution-errors

  • Tversky, A., & Kahnemean, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., & Griskevicius, V. (2009). Microbes, mating, and morality: Individual differences in three functional domains of disgust. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 103–122.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, W. W., & Ouwerkerk, J. W. (2014). Striving for positive self-evaluation as a motive for schadenfreude. In W. W. van Dijk & J. W. Ouwerkerk (Eds.), Schadenfreude: Understanding pleasure at the misfortune of others (pp. 131–148). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, W. W., Ouwerkerk, J. W., Goslinga, S., & Nieweg, M. (2005). Deservingness and schadenfreude. Cognition and Emotion, 19, 933–939.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, W. W., Ouwerkerk, J. W., Goslinga, S., Nieweg, M., & Gallucci, M. (2006). When people fall from grace: Reconsidering the role of envy in Schadenfreude. Emotion, 6, 156–160.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, S., Lilienfeld, S., & Rochat, P. (2018). Schadenfreude deconstructed and reconstructed: A tripartite motivational model. New Ideas in Psychology, 52, 1–11.

  • Wassens, R. (2013). Stapel speaks. Retrieved from: https://universonline.nl/2013/04/29/stapel-speaks

  • Weiner, B. (1995). Judgments of responsibility: A foundation for a theory of social conduct. New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, B. (2004). Social motivation and moral emotions. In M. J. Martinko (Ed.), Attribution theory: An organizational perspective (pp. 5–24). Delray Beach: St. Lucie Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mariëtte Berndsen.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that there are no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article

Ethical approval

All procedures performed in studies involving human participants were in accordance with the ethical standards of the institutional and/or national research committee and with the 1964 Helsinki declaration and its later amendments or comparable ethical standards.

Informed consent

Informed consent was obtained from all individual participants included in the studies.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Study 1

Single immoral act

John is a 48 year old American. This year John invested a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. John cheats for the first time on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. He does not pay the $37,000 he should to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Same immoral acts

John is a 48 year old American. Every year John invests a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. John cheats every year on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. This year he should have paid $37,000 to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Different immoral acts

John is a 48 year old American. He often engages in shoplifting and lying. This year John invested a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. This year John also cheats for the first time on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. He does not pay the $37,000 he should to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Single immoral act and moral act

John is a 48 year old American who has recently donated a considerable amount of money to charity. This year John invested a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. John cheats for the first time on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. He does not pay the $37,000 he should to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Same immoral acts and moral act

John is a 48 year old American who has recently donated a considerable amount of money to charity. Every year John invests a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. John cheats every year on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. This year he should have paid $37,000 to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Different immoral acts and moral act

John is a 48 year old American who has recently donated a considerable amount of money to charity. He often engages in shoplifting and lying. This year John invested a large sum of money in a foreign bank. When depositing money in a foreign bank account, citizens have to pay United States tax on the interest received from the bank. This year John also cheats for the first time on the tax-return form by omitting the interest received. He does not pay the $37,000 he should to the tax office. John is caught by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). John has to pay his $37,000 plus a fine (40% of $37,000) of $14,800.

Study 2

Single immoral act

John is a 48 year old American. He has been married to Fiona for 20 years.

John is on a conference in Europe and attends the dinner on the last day of the conference. After dinner, a band starts playing dancing music and John asks a young woman to dance. She introduces herself as Carol. Half an hour later they go to her hotel room. For the first time in his life, John has a one-night stand.

While they are asleep, a phone rings. Carol mistakenly picks up the phone, wrongly assuming that it is her mobile that rings, and answers with a groggy morning voice “Hello, Carol speaking …”. There is a silence at the other end of the phone, then Fiona yells “Who the hell are you!?” and slams her phone down. A little later, Fiona phones John and tells him not to come home for at least a month.

Same immoral acts

John is a 48 year old American. He has been married to Fiona for 20 years.

John is on a conference in Europe and attends the dinner on the last day of the conference. After dinner, a band starts playing dancing music and John asks a young woman to dance. She introduces herself as Carol. Half an hour later they go to her hotel room. John has a one-night stand. John has a long history of one-night stands.

While they are asleep, a phone rings. Carol mistakenly picks up the phone, wrongly assuming that it is her mobile that rings, and answers with a groggy morning voice “Hello, Carol speaking …”. There is a silence at the other end of the phone, then Fiona yells “Who the hell are you!?” and slams her phone down. A little later, Fiona phones John and tells him not to come home for at least a month.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berndsen, M., Tiggemann, M. Multiple versus single immoral acts: an immoral person evokes more schadenfreude than an immoral action. Motiv Emot 44, 738–754 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-020-09843-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-020-09843-5

Keywords

Navigation