Skip to main content
Log in

The geometry of visual space and the nature of visual experience

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some recently popular accounts of perception account for the phenomenal character of perceptual experience in terms of the qualities of objects. My concern in this paper is with naturalistic versions of such a phenomenal externalist view. Focusing on visual spatial perception, I argue that naturalistic phenomenal externalism conflicts with a number of scientific facts about the geometrical characteristics of visual spatial experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here, and in what follows, my use of ‘in virtue of’ signifies a constitutive relation.

  2. See Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996).

  3. In what follows I shall use the term object as an umbrella term.

  4. This strategy is implicit in the works of externalist representationalists such as Tye (1995, 2000, 2002), and naïve realists such as Martin (2002) and Campbell (2002). For explicit discussions of it see Fish (2009) and Langsam (2011).

  5. This intuition is often put as the claim that experience is transparent.

  6. See McDowell (1994, 2008) for a defense and Wright (2002, 2008) for a counter.

  7. Drawing on empirical findings and actual cases many have argued that phenomenal externalist views are problematic. See Block (2007, 2010), Pautz (2006, 2010), Peacocke (1997). Many have also relied on thought experiments to do so. See Block (1990), Chalmers (2006, 2011), and Thompson (2003).

  8. Chalmers Ibid. Thompson Ibid.

  9. I shall explain what I mean by this in the relevant section.

  10. Here and elsewhere by “experience” I mean perceptual experience unless otherwise indicated.

  11. See Jackson (1977) for an instructive discussion of various ways to define a direct object.

  12. On some views, perceptual experiences can have aspects that do not pertain to presenting qualities as qualities of objects. An example can help clarify this idea. Suppose that you are projecting an image on a screen. Compare two cases that you might say that you have a blurry visual experiences of the image. In the first case you experience the image as blurry, but in the second case experience it as perceived in a blurry manner; you do not experience the image as blurry. Your response to the first type of experience is to adjust the projector to get a sharper image. Your response to the second case might be to seek your eyeglasses. In the former cases blurriness would belong to the presentational phenomenal character of experience, but in the second case it would not. In the first case we can say that blurriness is part of the presentational phenomenal character of your experience. In the second case although blurriness is an aspect of the phenomenal character of your experience, it is not part of its presentational aspect. Those who are skeptical about the distinction are so probably because they think all cases of blurriness are presentational blurriness.

  13. For the ease of exposition, I shall henceforth use “the properties of objects” in place of the “directly perceived properties and relations of objects”. The two locution should be taken as equivalent unless otherwise indicated.

  14. See Jackson (1977) for an instructive discussion of various ways to define a direct object.

  15. Proponents of these accounts do not always explicitly articulate this commitment. But the commitment is obvious given the way these accounts explain the qualitative character of experience.

  16. See, for instance, Ayer (1956) and Russell (1997).

  17. Campbell (2002), Martin (2002). Naïve realists often hold that the metaphysical nature of non-veridical experiences need not be the same as veridical experiences. Their commitment to Inheritance is thus restricted to veridical experiences. Similarly, externalist representationalists who hold that perceptual experience is a matter of representing objects and their properties hold that.

  18. Dretske (1995), Harman (1990), and Tye (1995, 2000)

  19. Lycan (2001).

  20. Chalmers (2004), Thompson (forthcominga, b).

  21. McDowell (1984) and Travis (2005) dispute the reading of Frege that attributes to him what I am calling a Fregean view.

  22. Non-relationalism can be divided into adverbial and state views. Chisholm (1957), Sellars (1963), and Kriegel (2007) defend adverbial views. Block (1996, 2003) defends the state view.

  23. Shoemaker (1994, 2001, 2003) and Kriegel (2002, 2011) hold that colors are mind-dependent in the sense that they are dispositions to cause this or that type of experience. On neither of these views colors are mind-independent in the sense that I am using.

  24. See Masrour (forthcoming) for an extended defense of this claim.

  25. Euclid’s version of the fifth postulate is slightly different, but it has been proven that it is equivalent to what is now called the parallel postulate.

  26. Helmholtz showed that when subjects are asked to organize three points on a straight line the resulting configuration depends on the distance of the points from the observer’s point of view; it is concave for near points, convex for far points and straight for points located in intermediate distances.

  27. Wagner (2005) provides an excellent summary of the literature on this topic.

  28. The experiments where performed in a dark room.

  29. We have to make the additional assumption that the projections are symmetric around the X axis.

  30. Higashiyama et al. (1990), Indow, Inoie, and Matsushima (1962a, b), and Indow and Watanabe (1988) replicated Blumenfeld’s results.

  31. The horizontal panel is an imaginary plane that passes through the subject’s eyes and extends forward parallel to the ground.

  32. Foley performed the experiments two times, varying the distance of A from the subject. The average ratios were respectively 1.23 and 1.20 for the large and small configurations.

  33. See Koenderink et al. (2002, 2008, 2010).

  34. Shoemaker (2001).

  35. For an extended defense of this claim see Masrour (under review).

  36. See for example Tye (2009). I owe this last point to a discussion with Adam Pautz.

  37. For example, see the exchange between McDowell (1994, 2008) and Wright (2002, 2008).

References

  • Ayer, A. J. (1956). The problem of knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19–49.

  • Block, N. (2003). Mental paint. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of tyler burge. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Block, N. (2007). Wittgenstein and Qualia. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 73–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues, 20, 23–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenfeld, W. (1913). Untersuchungen über die scheinbare Grosse in Schraume. Zeitshrift fur Psychologie, 65, 241–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2004). The representational character of experience. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2011). The character of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, J. M. (1972). The size-distance relation and the intrinsic geometry of visual space: Implications for processing. Vision Research, 12, 323–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. (1962/1866). Physiological optics (trans: Southall, J. P. C.). New York: Dover.

  • Higashiyama, A. (1984). Curvature of binocular visual space: A modified method of right triangle. Vision Research, 24, 1713–1718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higashiyama, A., Ishikawa, T., & Tanaka, K. (1990). Visual alleys as a function of instructions under informative and reduced conditions of viewing. Perception & psychophysics, 47(5), 468–476.

  • Hill, C. (2009). Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hillebrand, F. (1902). Theorie der scheinbaren Grosse beim binokularen Sehen’, Denkschrift der Kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften Wien. Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Classe, 72, 255–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Indow, T., Inoue, E., & Matsushima, K. (1962a). An experimental study of the Luneburg theory of binocular space perception (l), The 3- and 4-point experiments. Japanese Psychological Research, 4, 6–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Indow, T., Inoue, E., & Matsushima, K. (1962b). An experimental study of the luneburg theory of binocular space perception (2), the alley experiments. Japanese Psychological Research, 4, 17–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Indow, T., & Watanabe, T. (1988). Alleys on an extensive frontoparallel plane: A second experiment. Perception, 17, 647–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ivry, R. B., & Cohen, A. (1987). The perception of doubly curved surfaces from intersecting contours. Perception & psychophysics, 41(4), 293–302.

  • Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenderink, J., et al. (2002). Large-scale visual frontoparallels under full-cue conditions. Perception, 31, 1467–1475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenderink, J., et al. (2008). Exocentric pointing in depth. Vision Research, 48, 716–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenderink, J., et al. (2010). Does monocular visual space contain planes? Acta Psychologia, 134, 40–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2002). Phenomenal content. Erkenntnis, 57, 175–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2007). Intentional inexistence and phenomenal intentionality. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 307–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2011). The sources of intentionality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langsam, H. (2011). The wonder of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luneburg, R. K. (1947). Mathematical analysis of binocular vision. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Luneburg, R. K. (1948). Metric methods in binocular visual perception, Studies and Essays. Courant Anniversary Volume, 215–240.

  • Luneburg, R. K. (1950). The metric of binocular visual space. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 40, 637–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (2001). The case for phenomenal externalism. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 17–35.

  • MacLeod, D., & Willen, J. (1995). Is there a visual space? In R. D. Luce & D’Zmura (Eds.), Geometric representations of perceptual phenomena. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17, 376–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1984). De re senses. In C. Wright (Ed.), Frege: Tradition and influence. Oxford: Blackwell Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2008). The disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument. In F. Macpherson & A. Haddock (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action, knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2006). Sensory awareness is not a wide physical relation: An empirical argument against externalist intentionalism. Nous, 40, 205–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2010). Do theories of consciousness rest on a mistake? Philosophical Issues, 20, 333–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1997). Sensation and the content of experience: A distinction. The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, 341.

  • Russell, B. (1997). The problems of philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. Originally published 1912.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Phenomenalism. In Science Sellars (Ed.), Perception and reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1994). Self-knowledge and “inner sense”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 249–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2001). Introspection and phenomenal character. Philosophical Topics, 28, 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2003). Content, character and color. Philosophical Issues, 13, 253–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1995). Some foundational problems in the theory of visual space. In R. D. Luce & D’Zmura (Eds.), Geometric representations of perceptual phenomena. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, B. (2003). The nature of phenomenal content. PhD Dissertation.

  • Travis, C. (2005). Frege, father of disjunctivism. Philosophical Topics, 33, 307–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2002). Representationalism and the transparency of experience. Nous, 36(1), 137–151.

  • Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, M. (1985). The metric of visual space. Perception and Psychophysics, 38, 483–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, M. (2005). The geometries of visual space. London: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2002). Anti-sceptics simple and subtle: G.E. Moore and John McDowell. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65, 330–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2008). Comment on John McDowell’s ‘the disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument’. In A. Haddock & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action and knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Farid Masrour.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Masrour, F. The geometry of visual space and the nature of visual experience. Philos Stud 172, 1813–1832 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0390-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0390-0

Keywords

Navigation