Skip to main content
Log in

The justification of reconstructive and reproductive memory beliefs

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Preservationism is a dominant account of the justification of beliefs formed on the basis of memory. According to preservationism, a memory belief is justified only if that belief was justified when it was initially held. However, we now know that much (if not most) of what we remember is not explicitly stored, but instead reconstructed when we attempt to recall it. Since reconstructive memory beliefs may not have been continuously held by the agent, or never held before at all, a purely preservationist account of memory does not allow for justified reconstructed memory beliefs. In this essay, I show how a process reliabilist account can maintain preservationism about reproductive memory beliefs while accommodating the justification of reconstructive memory beliefs. I argue that reconstructive memory is an inferential process, and that therefore the beliefs it produces are justified in the same way that other inferential beliefs are justified. Accordingly, my process reliabilist account combines a preservationist account of reproductive memory with an inferential account of reconstructive memory. I end by defending this view against objections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, unless otherwise stated, I am interested in prima facie justification.

  2. Many preservationists claim that knowledge is preserved, but I am focused on the weaker claim about justification. See Lackey (2005) for compelling arguments against knowledge preservation.

  3. As we will see, it is somewhat strained to call inferentialism an account of the justification of memory beliefs, per se. Rather, it is an application of a general view of justification to cases of memory beliefs.

  4. I am interested in doxastic, rather than propositional, justification. In what follows, I use “basis” to mean causal basis. In the definitions below, believing P on the basis of memory at t means that the subject’s belief that P at t is a result of a memory process. A belief with a particular causal basis will have different justificatory bases depending on which of the views below is accepted. For example, according to inferentialism, the justificatory basis for a memory belief is not memorial at all.

  5. Some externalist foundationalists will add a requirement that seeming to remember is a reliable process. See Plantinga (1993).

  6. This explication of the view is neutral on what it takes for a subject to have evidence as well as what counts as evidence.

  7. This kind of objection is given by Senor (1993), Goldman (1999), and Huemer (1999).

  8. A committed foundationalist might bite the bullet here and accept the result that you are justified in these beliefs. For example, Schroer (2008) claims that if you must accept it in order to take the foundationalist position seriously at all. At that point, the argument is at somewhat of a stalemate.

  9. Something like: “I have an apparent memory belief that, in the past, most of my apparent memory beliefs have turned out to be true.”

  10. The precise number of distinct memory systems, details about their nature, and their realization in the brain are all hotly contested. However, the details I rely on are relatively uncontroversial.

  11. Another way of establishing that different brain areas are responsible is by using brain imaging. An examination of that evidence is beyond the scope of this paper, but see Gabrieli (1998) for a review.

  12. Of course, one may not believe the output of a reconstructive memory process; however, I will focus only on beliefs here.

  13. What kind of content traces have is controversial. I wish to remain neutral on this question. If they have belief-like content, then their justificatory status should be taken into account as well.

  14. More precisely, the output beliefs are produced shortly afterward given that processes take some time to complete.

  15. Michaelian (2011) suggests process reliabilism as an account of reconstructive memory. His account does not distinguish between synchronic and diachronic belief-dependent processes.

  16. By ‘basis,’ I mean psychological basis.

  17. Of course, in any actual case, there will be more beliefs used, but as long as they are all justified, the memory belief is justified. Additionally, non-belief factors, such as a memory trace of my experience of the books on the desk might or might not be instrumental in the reconstruction.

  18. For the time being, let us assume that the stored representations are not beliefs.

References

  • Brewer, W., & Treyens, J. (1981). Role of schemata in memory for places. Cognitive Psychology, 13(2), 207–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleary, A. M. (2008). Recognition memory, familiarity, and déjà vu experiences. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17(5), 353–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubelli, R. (2010). A new taxonomy of memory and forgetting. In S. D. Salla (Ed.), Forgetting. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabrieli, J. D. (1998). Cognitive neuroscience of human memory. Annual Review of Psychology, 49(1), 87–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallo, D. A. (2010). False memories and fantastic beliefs: 15 years of the DRM illusion. Memory and Cognition, 38(7), 833–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1979/2008). What is justified belief? In Sosa, E., Kim, J., Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (Eds.), Epistemology: An Anthology, Chapter 29 (2nd ed., pp. 333–347). New York: Wiley. (Reprinted from George Pappas (Ed.), 1979, Justification and knowledge. Boston: D. Reidel).

  • Goldman, A. I. (1999). Internalism exposed. The Journal of Philosophy, 96(6), 271–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hemmer, P., & Steyvers, M. (2009). Integrating episodic and semantic information in memory for natural scenes. In Proceedings of the 31th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 1557–1562). TX: Cognitive Science Society Austin.

  • Huemer, M. (1999). The problem of memory knowledge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 80(4), 346–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (2007). Remembering: Metacognitive monitoring and control processes. In Science of memory: concepts (pp. 243-246). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Lackey, J. (2005). Memory as a generative epistemic source. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(3), 636–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewittness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 550–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F. (2005). Planting misinformation in the human mind: A 30-year investigation of the malleability of memory. Learning and Memory, 12(4), 361–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (2009). Perception and basic beliefs: Zombies, modules, and the problem of the external world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C., & Deutscher, M. (1966). Remembering. The Philosophical Review, 75, 161–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazzoni, G., & Memon, A. (2003). Imagination can create false autobiographical memories. Psychological Science, 14, 186–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2011). Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology, 24(3), 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper functioning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roediger, H., & McDermott, K. (1995). Creating false memories: Remembering words not presented in lists. Journal of Experimental Psychology-Learning Memory and Cognition, 21(4), 803–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L., Guerin, S. A., & Jacques, P. L. S. (2011). Memory distortion: An apaptive perpective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(10), 467–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L., & Tulving, E. (1994). What are the memory systems of 1994? In D. L. Schater & E. Tulving (Eds.), Memory systems, Chapter 1 (pp. 1–38). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroer, R. (2008). Memory foundationalism and the problem of unforgotten carelessness. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89(1), 74–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senor, T. D. (1993). Internalistic foundationalism and the justification of memory belief. Synthese, 94(3), 453–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2002). Episodic memory: From mind to brain. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2005). Concepts of memory. In E. Tulving & F. Craik (Eds.), The oxford handbook of memory, Chapter 2 (p. 33-3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Alvin Goldman, Preston Greene, Jack Lyons, Susanna Schellenberg, and an anonymous referee for their helpful comments and guidance on drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank audiences at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference, National University of Singapore as well as the Rutgers philosophy and cognitive science graduate students for their helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mary Salvaggio.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Salvaggio, M. The justification of reconstructive and reproductive memory beliefs. Philos Stud 175, 649–663 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0886-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0886-5

Keywords

Navigation