Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

I argue that Open Theism leads to a retreat from ascribing to God ‘complete omniscience’. Having surrendered this ground, the Open Theist cannot but retreat from ascribing to God complete omnipotence; the Open Theist must admit that God might perform actions which He reasonably expected would meet certain descriptions but which nevertheless do not do so. This then makes whatever goodness (in the sense of beneficence, not just benevolence) God has a matter of luck. Open Theism is committed to a partially ignorant God, one who is subject to the vagaries of luck for the efficacy of at least some of His actions and for His goodness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Flint T. (1998). Divine providence: The molinist account. Cornell, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker W. (1989). God, time and knowledge. Cornell, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker W. (1995). Middle knowledge: A refutation revisited. Faith and Philosophy 12, 223–236

    Google Scholar 

  • Helm P. (1988). Eternal God: A study of God without time. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow B. (1991). Time and eternity. Cornell, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow B. (2005a). No best world: Moral luck. Religious Studies 41(2): 165–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leftow B. (2005b). No best world: Creaturely freedom. Religious Studies 41(3): 269–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemmon E. (1966). Sentences, statements and propositions. In: Williams B., Montefiore A. (eds), British analytical philosophy. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas J. (1973). A treatise on time and space. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mawson T.J. (2001). Miracles and laws of nature. Religious Studies 37, 33–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mawson T.J. (2005a). Freedom, human and divine. Religious Studies 41, 55–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mawson, T. J. (2005b). Belief in God. Oxford: OUP.

  • Metcalf T. (2004). Omniscience and maximal power. Religious Studies 40, 289–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morriston W. (2003). Are omnipotence and necessary moral perfection compatible? Reply to Mawson. Religious Studies 39, 441–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morriston W. (2005). Power, liability, and the free will defence, reply to Mawson. Religious Studies 41, 71–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinnock C., et al. (1994). The openness of God: A biblical challenge to the traditional understanding of God. InterVarsity and Paternoster Press, Downers, Grove and Carlisle

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga A. (1986). On Ockham’s way out. Faith and Philosophy 3: 235–269

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne R. (1977). The coherence of Theism. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne R. (1994). The Christian God. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne R. (2001). Epistemic justification. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Taliaferro C (ed) (1998). Contemporary philosophy of religion. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to T. J. Mawson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mawson, T.J. Divine eternity. Int J Philos Relig 64, 35–50 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-008-9162-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-008-9162-0

Keywords

Navigation