Skip to main content
Log in

Keep the chickens cooped: the epistemic inadequacy of free range metaphysics

  • S.I.: New Metaphysics of Science
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper aims to better motivate the naturalization of metaphysics by identifying and criticizing a class of theories I call ’free range metaphysics’. I argue that free range metaphysics is epistemically inadequate because the constraints on its content—consistency, simplicity, intuitive plausibility, and explanatory power—are insufficiently robust and justificatory. However, since free range metaphysics yields clarity-conducive techniques, incubates science, and produces conceptual and formal tools useful for scientifically engaged philosophy, I do not recommend its discontinuation. I do recommend, however, ending the discipline’s bad faith. That is, I urge that free range metaphysics not be taken to have fully satisfactory epistemic credentials over and above its pragmatic ones.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Callender (2011), French (2014), French and McKenzie (2012), Maclaurin and Dyke (2012), Ladyman et al. (2013), and Morganti (2013).

  2. On scientific metaphysics, see Calosi and Morganti (2016), Dorato (2015), Dorato and Morganti (2013), Ereshefsky (2010), Ereshefsky and Pedroso (2013), Kistler (2010), Loewer (2012), Maudlin (2007), Morganti (2008), Ney (2012), Ney and Albert (2013), Norton (2015), Pradeu and Guay (2015), Ruetsche (2011), Waters (2017), and the other contributions to this issue.

  3. I thank Jesse Prinz for this last point.

  4. An anonymous reviewer brings to my attention a possible comparison between free range metaphysics and pure mathematics. However, I think the two are unlike one another in some important respects. First, while free range metaphysics is not a priori (see Sect. 2.4 below), I take pure mathematics to be—not in the naive sense of it being completely independent of experience, but in the sense that it proceeds from the armchair, without being substantially constrained by empirical beliefs or evidence. Second, I take free range metaphysics to make substantive claims about the world; I take pure mathematics not to. However, I don’t have the space to defend these contentious claims about mathematics here.

  5. I do not mean to suggest that the topic makes a metaphysical theory free range or otherwise. It is, rather, a matter of how the theory is constructed. Granted, there may be some metaphysical topics that belong to free range metaphysics necessarily—topics that science has no bearing on in principle. It would be difficult to know which topics science cannot speak to in principle, since the course of inquiry is unpredictable and since our modal judgments about the capacities of science are not very reliable (see Ladyman et al. 2007, p. 16). But we can say, for instance, that the nature of the forms belongs necessarily to free range metaphysics. Still, it remains the case that metaphysical inquiries that investigate topics necessarily alien to science are free range insofar as they proceed independently of science.

    The topic of investigation is also important to the extent that it constrains the process of naturalization. Whether there are presently discoverable points of contact between science and some metaphysical theory depends, among other things, on the topic of the metaphysical theory. In particular, it depends on whether the domain of science overlaps with the domain of the metaphysical theory, or whether any scientific evidence is relevant to the metaphysical subject-matter, or whether scientific practices or concepts or heuristics can be usefully applied in our investigations of the metaphysical subject-matter. So the topic of inquiry partly determines whether some metaphysical theory can be naturalized or not. Still, whether it is naturalized or not depends on the actual methods used in its formulation.

  6. Bennett (2009) argues that, in certain cases, the criteria do not much help with theory selection. She shows that in some metaphysical debates “there are few grounds for choosing” between rival theories, because measures of simplicity trade off against one another and because the problems that arise for one arise for the other in one form or another (original emphasis, 2009, p. 73). In those cases, she claims, we have “little justification” for believing either view (2009, p. 42). Her claim is localized to the particular metaphysical debates she takes pains to describe. My claim here is broader. Moreover, my argument focuses not on trade-offs of simplicity or pervasive problems, but on the weakness of the theoretical constraints on free range metaphysics.

  7. Compare Kriegel (2013). Kriegel argues that in revisionary metaphysics, what we take to be theoretical virtues (including, inter alia, simplicity and intuitiveness) fail to be truth-conducive. By contrast, my present concern is not with truth-conduciveness, but rather, with the aptness of such virtues (or constraints, in my terminology) to robustly constrain theoretical content and secure epistemic warrant.

  8. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  9. Note that the apple theory, while it is a metaphysical theory of sorts, isn’t a serious metaphysical theory. It is not meant to be reflective of actual metaphysical practice. Actual metaphysical theories are subject to further constraints. So the example does not commit me to any assumptions about the methods or aims of metaphysics. Rather, it is an example of a theory that we explicitly hold accountable only to the consistency constraint, which allows us to isolate and evaluate that constraint.

  10. Of course, the success of the demonstration hinges on our accepting the evidence of our senses. I assume that we should.

  11. There is, of course, a whole literature on intuition (see Chudnoff 2014 for an overview). At this juncture, I don’t mean to commit to any view of what intuitions are or what the term means—I’m just stipulating.

  12. Dorr (2010) claims that intuition-talk by metaphysicians is a kind of humble rhetoric that signals assumptions, rather than being evidential. See Eklund (2013) and Maclaurin and Dyke (2012) for replies.

  13. See Devitt (2012) for a critical response to some of this work.

  14. One might object: it is not clear that there is a dedicated module for scientific intuition, either — a module that would have been beneficial for individual survival and reproduction. I thank an anonymous reviewer for the objection. I agree that there is not obviously a sui generis module for scientific intuition. But scientific theories do not rest on some scientific analog of metaphysical intuition. While some metaphysical speculation rests on metaphysical intuition, scientific theory typically does not bottom out in scientific intuition. Rather, it rests on evidence that we gather using capacities that we do have evolved neural systems for: perceptual systems, systems that enable action and intervention, and so forth.

  15. For further arguments against the evidential value of metaphysical intuitions, see Kriegel (2013).

  16. For this point, I thank an audience member at my presentation of this work at the Canadian Philosophical Association Annual Congress on May 31, 2015 in Ottawa.

  17. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

  18. Note that this argument is not probabilistic. It makes no claim about the probability of current or future metaphysical intuitions turning out to be false. It simply denounces a form of evidence on the basis of its systematic unreliability. So the base rate fallacy does not threaten here.

  19. See Ladyman (2012) for a comparison of the role of explanation in metaphysics and in science.

  20. I say ‘putatively explain’ in case the reader thinks explanations must be factive. If they must be factive, then there is an epistemic problem with regard to the conditions under which we can know something to be an explanation. But at any rate, what we care about is putative explanations, since it will be those that constrain our theories. We will permit into the theory what we take to be explanatory.

  21. While Salmon and Kitcher account for scientific explanation, the central thrust of their views might help us flesh out how metaphysical explanation can be lovely in Lipton’s sense.

  22. For this point, I thank an audience member at my talk “No Escape for No Miracles: The No-Miracles Argument and The Base-Rate Fallacy” at the Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of ScienceAnnual Meeting on May 28, 2016 in Calgary.

  23. That is why scientific theories, such as Darwin’s evolutionary theory, whose success is primarily a function of their explanatory power, are not free range theories.

  24. Note that my use of the phrase ‘collateral benefits’ here echoes Maclaurin and Dyke (2012).

  25. The unpublished paper is called On the Relation Between Philosophy and Science and can be found at the following URL: http://petergodfreysmith.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/06/PhilosophyScience_PGS_2013_C.pdf.

  26. French made this remark following his talk “Between Humeanism and Dispostionalism; or, How to Construct a Modal Framework for Modern Science by Appropriating Metaphysical Devices” at the conference New Trends in the Metaphysics of Science on December 17, 2015.

References

  • Andow, J. (2016). Reliable but not home free? What framing effects mean for moral intuitions. Philosophical Psychology, 6, 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2009). Composition, colocation, and metaontology. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 38–76). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2016). There is no special problem with metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 173, 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2011). Philosophy of science and metaphysics. In S. French & J. Saatsi (Eds.), The continuum companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 33–54). New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Morganti, M., (2016). Humean supervenience, composition as identity and quantum wholes. Erkenntnis, 81(6), 1173–1194.

  • Chudnoff, E. (2014). Intuition. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombo, M. (2016). Experimental philosophy of explanation rising: The case for a plurality of concepts of explanation. Cognitive Science, 40(4), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Sider, T. (2005). Riddles of existence: A guided tour of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2013). The objects of thought. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2012). Whither experimental semantics? Theoria, 27(1), 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2015). Relying on intuitions: Where cappelen and deutsch go wrong. Inquiry, 58(7–8), 669–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2015). Events and the ontology of quantum mechanics. Topoi, 34(2), 369–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M., & Morganti, M. (2013). Grades of individuality: A pluralistic view of identity in quantum mechanics and in the sciences. Philosophical Studies, 163(3), 591–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C. (2010). Review: Every thing must go. Notre Dame Philosophical Review. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24377-every-thing-must-go-metaphysics-naturalized/.

  • Eklund, M. (2006). Neo-fregean ontology. Philosophical Perspectives, 20(Metaphysics), 95–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, M. (2013). Trends and progress in philosophy. Metaphilosophy, 44(3), 276–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 77(5), 674–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Pedroso, M. (2013). Biological individuality: The case of biofilms. Biology and Philosophy, 28(2), 331–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1(1), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & McKenzie, K. (2012). Thinking outside the toolbox: Towards a more productive engagement between metaphysics and philosophy of physics. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 8(1), 42–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2014). Philosophy of biology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2007). Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2010). Critical notice of every thing must go. Metascience, 19(2), 174–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kistler, M. (2010). Mechanisms and downward causation. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 595–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Scientific Explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Kriegel, U. (2013). The epistemological challenge of revisionary metaphysics. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(12), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2012). Science, metaphysics, and method. Philosophical Studies, 160, 21–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., & Kincaid, H. (Eds.). (2013). Scientific Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 115–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1998). The possibility of metaphysics: Substance, identity, and time. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92, B1–B12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., & Stephen, S. (2012). The role of experiment in the philosophy of language. In G. Russell & D. Graff Fara (Eds.), Routledge companion to philosophy of language (pp. 495–512). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, J., & Dyke, H. (2012). What is analytic metaphysics for? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(2), 291–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, M., & Parsons, J. (2013). Maclaurin and dyke on analytic metaphysics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(1), 173–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morganti, M. (2008). Weak discernibility, quantum mechanics and the generalist picture. Philosophica, 10(1/2), 155–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morganti, M. (2013). Combining science and metaphysics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2012). The status of our ordinary three dimensions in a quantum universe. Noûs, 46(3), 525–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A., & Albert, D. (Eds.). (2013). The wave function: Essays in the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs, 41(4), 663–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., Stich, S., & Weinberg, J. (2003). Metaskepticism: Meditations in ethnoepistemology. In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics (pp. 227–247). Burlington: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2015). Weak discernibility and relations between quanta. Philosophy of Science, 82(5), 1188–1199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17(3), 145–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T., & Guay, A. (2015). Individuals across the sciences. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2014). One: Being an investigation into the unity of reality and of its parts, including the singular object which is nothingness. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche, L. (2011). Interpreting quantum theories: The art of the possible. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton UP: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language, 27(2), 135–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shtulman, A., & Harrington, K. (2016). Tensions between science and across the lifespan. Topics in Cognitive Science, 8, 118–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Framing moral intuitions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, vol. 2: The cognitive science of morality (pp. 47–76). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. (2008). The instability of philosophical intuitions: Running hot and cold on truetemp. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 138–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1998). The statue and the clay. Noûs, 32(2), 149–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1981). The doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62(April), 123–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. (2017). No general structure. In M. Slatter and Z. Yudell (Eds.), Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science: New Essays (pp. 81–108) Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • Weinberg, J., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology, 23(2), 331–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29(1&2), 429–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16(10), 780–784.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiegmann, A., Okan, Y., & Nagel, J. (2012). Order effects in moral judgment. Philosophical Psychology, 25(6), 813–836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). Knowledge of metaphysical modality. In The Philosophy (Ed.), The philosophy of philosophy (pp. 134–179). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

  • Wimsatt, W. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 20(sup 1), 207–274.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Michael Devitt, Graham Priest, David Papineau, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Jesse Prinz, Barbara Montero, Stephen Neale, Yuval Abrams, Cosim Sayid, Derek Skillings, Jake Quilty-Dunn, Ross Colebrook, Kyle Blanchette, and Dustin Olson for invaluable feedback and helpful discussions of this work. I also thank my anonymous reviewers for their careful and insightful comments, from which this paper benefited greatly. Thanks to audiences at my presentations of this work at the Canadian Philosophical Association Annual Congress, May 31, 2015, in Ottawa and at New Trends in the Metaphysics of Science, December 16, 2015, in Paris. I would also like to thank the other presenters at New Trends in the Metaphysics of Science, whose illuminating and informative presentations shaped both this paper and my related work. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, award #752-2012-0363.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amanda Bryant.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bryant, A. Keep the chickens cooped: the epistemic inadequacy of free range metaphysics. Synthese 197, 1867–1887 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1398-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1398-8

Keywords

Navigation