Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Ignorance as a productive response to epistemic perturbations

  • Knowing the Unknown
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that ignorance, rather than being a result or representation of false beliefs or misinformation, is a compensatory epistemic adaptation of complex rhetoric systems. A rhetoric system is here defined as a set of interconnected rhetorical elements (beliefs, arguments, commonplaces [loci communes], meanings, and texts) that cohere into a self-organized system that is thoroughly “about” its contexts—meaning that its own boundaries and relations are both constrained and enabled by the contexts in which it exists. Ignorance, as described here, is epistemic management that preserves the boundaries and relations of a rhetoric system, and is a way of dealing with information that runs counter to one’s beliefs. Ignorance is also productive, in that it produces new knowledge that works to make rhetoric systems more resistant to potential destabilization. To elaborate these points, the paper examines discourse about the phenomenon of global climate change, which illustrates how individuals productively counter information as a way of preserving beliefs. As the paper argues, ignorance is neither a cognitive nor epistemological failure, but rather is a result of the dynamic and continuous process of enforcing epistemic and rhetorical boundaries.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In a more recent study by Nyhan et al. (2014), parents who were resistant to vaccinating their children because of a fear that vaccines cause autism, when presented with evidence that such vaccines do not cause autism, showed “decreased intent to vaccinate” (emphasis added).

  2. Relatedly, there is a significant amount of scholarship on ignorance that presents it as the result or representation of false beliefs or misinformation, which often also considers ignorance and belief in terms of quantity (Le Morvan and Peels 2016; Treaner 2013).

  3. There are similarities between epistemic management that results from ignorance and the management of uncertainty (see, for example, Hogg and Blaylock 2012, p. xxiii), a state that could be considered a form of tentative ignorance. While ignorance is explored in detail here, a full discussion of its overlaps with uncertainty is beyond the scope of this paper.

  4. We could go back to the Greek sophist Protagoras to find this point, as he held that there are two opposed logoi or rational accounts of any situation (Sprague 1972). More recent (and nuanced) articulations can be found in Consigney (1996) and Perelman (1982).

  5. Note that the use of the term “force” does not mean that this rhetorical force has to be a physical force. Complex systems theory describes several systems that are held together by a non-physical force. Social systems (e.g. Luhmann 1995) are just one example of such non-physical systems bound together in this way. The existence of such a force simply means that the borders cohere in a way that makes them resistant to destabilization or redefinition.

  6. Dimitrov and Woog (1997), for example, specifically discuss complex human society as a nonlinear dynamic world of emergence, bifurcations, attractors, autopoiesis, and self-organization (p. 502).

  7. For express consideration of both kinds of systems, see Prigogine (1996), Prigogine and Stengers (1984).

  8. In fact there is a great deal of significant neuroscientific evidence that our language use—and so our reasoning and our beliefs—are influenced by non-linguistic factors associated with our somatic emotional responses (Franks 2006).

  9. Rayner’s work echoes theories of humans as “cognitive misers” (Fiske and Taylor 1991) as well as the notion of motivated skepticism (Taber and Lodge 2006).

  10. Despite public opinion increasingly supporting the existence and the seriousness of AGW, significant opposition still does exist (Dunlap 2013, p. 695).

  11. See, for example, the recent “Pizzagate” incident, in which a restaurant in Washington, D.C. was thought to be a hub for human trafficking. Though completely fictitious, the strength of belief and intricacy of the narrative of proponents of the conspiracy drove one person to travel to the restaurant and fire his rifle in an attempt to disrupt the enterprise (Pizzagate conspiracy theory 2019).

References

  • Alcoff, L. M. (2007). Epistemologies of ignorance: Three types. In S. Sullivan & N. Tuana (Eds.), Race and epistemologies of ignorance (pp. 39–58). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alternative facts. (2019). Wikipedia.

  • Aristotle. (1984). The Rhetoric and the poetics of Aristotle (trans: Roberts, R., Bywater, I.). New York: Random House.

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2001). The emergence of contentful experience. In T. Kitamura (Ed.), What should be computed to understand and model brain function? (pp. 217–237). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, K. (1954). Permanence and change: An anatomy of purpose. 3rd ed. (1984). University of California Press.

  • Consigny, S. (1996). Edward schiappa’s reading of the sophists. Rhetoric Review, 14(2), 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Landa, M. (1997). A thousand years of nonlinear history. New York: Zone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophrenia (trans: Massumi, B.). University of Minnesota Press.

  • Dimitrov, V., & Woog, R. (1997). Studying social complexity: From Soft to virtual systems methodology. Complex Systems, 11, 501–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunlap, R. E. (2013). Climate change skepticism and denial: An introduction. American Behavioral Scientist, 57(6), 691–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. T., & Taylor, S. E. (1991). Social cognition. New York: McGraw.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, D. (2006). The neuroscience of emotions. In J. E. Stets & J. H. Turner (Eds.), Handbook of the sociology of emotions (pp. 38–62). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hawk, B. (2007). A counter-history of composition: Toward methodologies of complexity. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayles, N. K. (1999). How we became posthuman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hogg, M. A., & Blaylock, D. L. (2012). Preface: From uncertainty to extremism. In M. A. Hogg & D. L. Blaylock (Eds.), Extremism and the psychology of uncertainty (pp. 15–25). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S. (2008). Wild-agency: Nested intentionalities in neuroscience and archeology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 363(1499), 1981–1991.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S., & Day, B. (2015). Wild systems theory as a 21st century coherence framework for cognitive science. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 21(T). MIND Group.

  • Jordan, J. S., & Ghin, M. (2006). (Proto-) consciousness as a contextually-emergent property of self-sustaining systems. Mind Matter, 4, 45–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S., & Heidenreich, B. (2010). The intentional nature of self-sustaining systems. Mind & Matter, 8(1), 45–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S., & Mays, C. (2017). Wild meaning: The intercorporeal nature of objects, bodies, and words. In C. Meyer, J. Streeck, & J. S. Jordan (Eds.), Intercorporeality: Emerging socialities in interaction (pp. 361–378). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S., & Vinson, D. (2012). After nature: On bodies, consciousness, and causality. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19(5/6), 229–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. S., & Wesselmann, E. D. (2014). The contextually grounded nature of prosocial behavior: A multiscale, embodied approach to morality. In D. A. Schroeder & W. G. Graziano (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of prosocial behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (1995). At home in the universe: The search for the laws of self-organization and complexity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Morvan, P., & Peels, R. (2016). The nature of ignorance: Two views. In R. Peels & M. Blaauw (Eds.), The epistemic dimensions of ignorance (pp. 12–32). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1995). Social systems (trans: Bednarz, J. Jr., Baecker, D.). Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mays, C. (2013). Who’s driving this thing, anyway? Emotion and language in rhetoric and neuroscience. JAC: A Journal of Rhetoric, Culture and Politics, 33(1–2), 473–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mays, C. (2015). From “Flows” to “Excess”: On stability, stubbornness, and blockage in rhetorical ecologies. Enculturation, 19 pp.

  • McGoey, L. (2014). Strategic unknowns: Towards a sociology of ignorance. In L. McGoey (Ed.), An introduction to the sociology of ignorance (pp. 1–16). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyhan, B., & Reifler, J. (2006). When corrections fail: The presistence of political misperceptions. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, pp. 303–330.

  • Nyhan, B., et al. (2014). Effective messages in vaccine promotion: A randomized trial. Pediatrics, 133(4), 835–842.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peels, R. (2017). Introduction. In R. Peels (Ed.), Perspectives on ignorance from moral and social philosophy (pp. 1–14). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C. (1982). The realm of rhetoric. London: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1971). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation (trans: Wilkinson, J., Weaver, P.). University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Pizzagate conspiracy theory. (2019). Wikipedia.

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1984). Order out of Chaos: Man’s new dialogue with nature. London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1996). The end of certainty: Time, chaos, and the new laws of nature. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, S. (2014). Uncomfortable knowledge: The social construction of ignorance in science and environmental policy discourses. In L. McGoey (Ed.), An introduction to the sociology of ignorance (pp. 107–126). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2009). Ignorance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts-Miller, P. (2009). Dissent As ‘‘Aid and Comfort to the Enemy’’: The rhetorical power of Naïve Realism and ingroup identity. Rhetoric Society Quarterly, 39(2), 170–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohde, D. (2013). Held by the Taliban: A times reporter’s account. A five-part series by David Rohde. NYTimes.com. The New York Times Company.

  • Skinner, B. F. (1976). About behaviorism. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprague, R. K. (Ed.). (1972). The older sophists. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeck, J., & Jordan, J. S. (2009). Communication as a dynamical self-sustaining system: The importance of time-scales and nested contexts. Communication Theory, 19(4), 445–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, D. (2019). Dual atmospheric rivers in NorCal bring flood concerns & yet more Sierra snow. WeatherWest: The California Weather Blog.

  • Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2006). Motivated skepticism in the evaluation of political beliefs. American Journal of Political Science, 50(3), 755–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tavris, C., & Aronson, E. (2007). Mistakes were made (but not by me): Why we justify foolish beliefs, bad decisions, and Hurtful Acts. Harcourt.

  • Treaner, N. (2013). The measure of knowledge. Nous, 47(3), 577–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worsham, L. (2013). From the editor: Thinking with cats (more, to follow). JAC: A Journal of Rhetoric, Culture and Politics, 30(3–4), 407–433.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank readers of previous iterations of this paper, including the two anonymous reviewers whose feedback was invaluable in shaping the article manuscript. I would also like to thank the editors of this special issue of Synthese, Selene Arfini and Lorenzo Magnani, who provided feedback in conversation and correspondence that had a significant impact on the work. As well, I would like to thank Tommaso Bertolotti for putting together the 2018 Cognition in 3E conference, where the idea for this article emerged. I also wish to thank Tomie Hahn and Curtis Bahn for their useful feedback on earlier versions of this work. Finally, I would like to thank Julie Jung and J. Scott Jordan for countless discussions and suggestions regarding the direction and scope of my work in this area.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Mays.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mays, C. Ignorance as a productive response to epistemic perturbations. Synthese 198, 6491–6507 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02471-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02471-8

Keywords

Navigation