Skip to main content
Log in

“Formal” Versus “Empirical” Approaches to Quantum–Classical Reduction

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I distinguish two types of reduction within the context of quantum-classical relations, which I designate “formal” and “empirical”. Formal reduction holds or fails to hold solely by virtue of the mathematical relationship between two theories; it is therefore a two-place, a priori relation between theories. Empirical reduction requires one theory to encompass the range of physical behaviors that are well-modeled in another theory; in a certain sense, it is a three-place, a posteriori relation connecting the theories and the domain of physical reality that both serve to describe. Focusing on the relationship between classical and quantum mechanics, I argue that while certain formal results concerning singular \(\hbar \rightarrow 0\) limits have been taken to preclude the possibility of reduction between these theories, such results at most provide support for the claim that singular limits block reduction in the formal sense; little if any reason has been given for thinking that they block reduction in the empirical sense. I then briefly outline a strategy for empirical reduction that is suggested by work on decoherence theory, arguing that this sort of account remains a fully viable route to the empirical reduction of classical to quantum mechanics and is unaffected by such singular limits.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For further discussion of the Nagel/Schaffner approach to reduction, see, for example Dizadji-Bahmani et al. (2010).

  2. In (2007), Landsman offers a number of suggestions as to the particular measure of \(S_{cl}\) that might be adopted in various cases.

  3. Another reason often cited for the inability of quantum theory to recover classical chaos is that classical chaos entails exponential divergence of closely spaced initial conditions in phase space, while on the usual association of classical phase space points with narrow wave packet states in quantum theory, the unitary nature of the Schrodinger evolution—which preserves the inner product between any two initial states throughout their evolution—precludes such a divergence between the corresponding wave packets. However, Zurek has argued that when we incorporate the effects of environmental decoherence, the effective quantum dynamics of the system in question is no longer unitary (it is only the total closed system consisting of the system in question and its environment that is assumed to evolve unitarily) and so this objection no longer applies.

  4. For further discussion of the vagueness of existing formulations of the limit-based approach, see Rosaler (2015c).

  5. See Landsman’s (2007) for examples of non-singular \(\hbar \rightarrow 0\) limiting relations.

  6. See Joos et al. (2003), Ch. 3, Bacciagaluppi (2012) and Barbour (2000) Ch. 20 for discussion of this last example.

  7. Here, I take classical behavior to designate behavior that is accurately represented by some purely classical model. That is, I do not take it to include those systems whose behavior is well-described by semiclassical models that employ hybrids of quantum and classical concepts.

  8. A projection-valued measure (PVM) on a Hilbert space \(\mathcal {H}\) is a set of self-adjoint operators \(\{ {\hat{P}}_{\alpha } \}\) on \(\mathcal {H}\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned} \sum _{\alpha } {\hat{P}}_{\alpha } = {\hat{I}}, \end{aligned}$$
    (7)
    $$\begin{aligned} {\hat{P}}_{\alpha } {\hat{P}}_{\beta } = \delta _{\alpha \beta } {\hat{P}}_{\alpha }, \ \end{aligned}$$
    (8)

    where there is no summation over repeated indices in (8). The concept of a positive operator-valued measure (POVM) on \(\mathcal {H}\) generalizes the notion of a PVM by relaxing the requirement of orthogonality in (8). Thus, a positive-operator-valued measure (POVM) on a Hilbert space \(\mathcal {H}\) is a set \(\{ {\hat{\Pi }}_{\alpha } \}\) of positive operators such that

    $$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{\alpha } {\hat{\Pi }}_{\alpha } = {\hat{I}}. \end{aligned}$$
    (9)

    Recall that an operator \({\hat{O}}\) is positive if it is self-adjoint and \(\langle \Psi | {\hat{O}}|\Psi \rangle \ge 0 \) for every \(|\Psi \rangle \in \mathcal {H}\). Note that every PVM is also a POVM.

  9. It is important to note that the ensemble distribution \( \langle X | {\hat{\rho }}_{S}(t) | X \rangle \) reflects a distribution across branches, which originate in some initial narrow state \({\hat{\rho }}^{0}_{S}\).

References

  • Bacciagaluppi G (2012) The role of decoherence in quantum mechanics. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy. Winter 2012 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/qm-decoherence/

  • Barbour J (2000) The end of time: the next revolution in physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman R (2002) The devil in the details: asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Belot G (2005) Whose devil? Which details? Philos Sci 72(1):128–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berry M (1994) Asymptotics, singularities and the reduction of theories. In: Skyrms B, Prawitz D, Westerståhl D (eds) Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, IX: proceedings of the ninth international congress of logic, methodology and philosophy of science, Uppsala, Sweden, August 7–14, 1991 (Studies in logic and foundations of mathematics, vol 134), pp 597–607

  • Berry MV (1983) Semiclassical mechanics of regular and irregular motion. Les Houches Lect Ser 36:171–271

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich A (2008) Reexamining the quantum–classical relation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dizadji-Bahmani F, Frigg R, Hartmann S (2010) Who’s afraid of Nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis 73(3):393–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joos E, Zeh D, Kiefer C, Giulini D, Kupsch J, Stamatescu I-O (2003) Decoherence and the appearance of a classical world in quantum theory, 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landsman NP (2007) Between classical and quantum. In Butterfield J, Earman J (eds) Philosophy of physics (handbook of the philosophy of science), vol 1. Elsevier

  • Rosaler J (2015a) Interpretation neutrality in the classical domain of quantum theory. Under review (copy available on request)

  • Rosaler J (2015b) Is de Broglie–Bohm theory specially equipped to recover classical behavior? Philosophy of science (forthcoming)

  • Rosaler J (2015c) Local reduction in physics. Stud hist philos modern phys 50:54–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakurai JJ, Tuan SF, Commins ED (1995) Modern quantum mechanics. Am J Phys 63:93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer MA (2008) Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace D (2012) The emergent multiverse: quantum theory according to the everett interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek WH, Habib S, Paz JP (1993) Coherent states via decoherence. Phys Rev Lett 70(9):1187–1190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek WH, Paz JP (1995) Quantum chaos: a decoherent definition. Phys D Nonlinear Phenom 83(1):300–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zurek Wojciech H (1998) Decoherence, chaos, quantum–classical correspondence, and the algorithmic arrow of time. Phys Scr 1998(T76):186

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to David Wallace, Simon Saunders, Christopher Timpson, Jeremy Butterfield and Robert Batterman for many helpful discussions on the classical domain of quantum theory.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Rosaler.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosaler, J. “Formal” Versus “Empirical” Approaches to Quantum–Classical Reduction. Topoi 34, 325–338 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9328-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9328-1

Keywords

Navigation