Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

What is it to Share Contraceptive Responsibility?

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are three stages at which procreative outcomes can be prevented or altered: (1) prior to conception (2) during pregnancy and (3) after birth. Daniel Engster (Soc Theory Pract 36(2):233–262, 2010) has ably argued that plans to prevent or alter procreative outcomes at stages (2) and (3)—through abortion and adoption—introduce financial, physical, and emotional hardships to which women are disproportionately vulnerable. In this paper, I argue that plans to prevent or alter undesirable procreative outcomes at stage (1)—through contraception use—similarly disadvantage women. I suggest that accounts proposing moral responsibilities to delay or permanently avoid procreation are insufficiently attentive to the methods through which undesirable procreative outcomes might be prevented and how such methods unfairly burden women. In conclusion, I propose several ways that men and women might more equitably share contraceptive responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Because this paper is primarily concerned with reproductive responsibilities of heterosexual, cisgender men and women, I frequently use the terms “men”/”males” and “women”/”females” interchangeably (see Sect. 3.6).

  2. “Typical use” indicates the effectiveness of contraception used by the average person over time. “Perfect use” indicates the effectiveness of contraception used perfectly every time. Most people are not perfect users and should rely on typical use estimations.

  3. The term “trans*” inclusively refers to transgender men and women, agender, genderqueer, bi-gender, non-binary gender, etc.; “trans” without an asterisk refers specifically to transgender men or women.

  4. Originally quoted by Oudshoorn (2004, 357–359).

References

  • American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Adolescence (2014) Contraception for adolescents. Pediatrics 134:e1244–e1256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arras JD, Blustein J (1995) Reproductive responsibility and long-acting contraceptives. Hastings Cent Rep 25(1):S27–S29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D (1997) Why it is better never to come into existence. Am Philos Quart 34:345–355

    Google Scholar 

  • Brake E (2005) Fatherhood and child support: do men have a right to choose? J Appl Philos 22(1):55–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brault MA, Schensul SL, Singh R et al (2015) Multilevel perspectives on female sterilization in low-income communities in Mumbai, India. Qual Health Res. doi:10.1177/1049732315589744

    Google Scholar 

  • Budig M, England P (2001) The wage penalty for motherhood. Am Soc Rev 66(2):204–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S (2014)

  • Cain J, Lowell J, Thorndyke L et al (2000) Contraceptive requirements for clinical research. Obstet Gynecol 95(6, Part 1):861–866

    Google Scholar 

  • Campo-Engelstein L (2010) Autonomous contraception: science, sociology, and the potential of a male pill. Michigan State University Medical Humanities Report 32(2):1–8

  • Campo-Engelstein L (2013) Raging hormones, domestic incompetence, and contraceptive indifference: narratives contributing to the perception that women do not trust men to use contraception. Cult Health Sex 15(3):283–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campo-Engelstein L (2014) Paternal-fetal harm and men’s moral duty to use contraception: applying the principles of monmaleficence and beneficence to men’s reproductive responsibility. Med Stud 4(1–4):1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassidy L (2006) That many of us should not parent. Hypatia 21(4):40–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (2013) U.S. selected practice recommendations for contraceptive use. Morb Mortal Wkly Rep 62:1–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandra A (1998) Surgical sterilization in the United States: prevalence and characteristics, 1965–95. Vital Health Stat Ser 23 Data Natl Surv Fam Growth 20:1–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng C, Mruk D (2010) New frontiers in nonhormonal male contraception. Contraception 82(5):476–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis A (1981) Women, race, and class. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Djerassi C (1989) The bitter pill. Science 245(4916):356–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dresser R (1996) Long-term contraceptives in the criminal justice system. In: Moskowitz E, Jennings B (eds) Coerced contraception: moral and policy challenges of long-acting birth control. Georgetown, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Dugdale A (1995) Devices and desires: constructing the intrauterine device, 1908–1988. Dissertation, University of Wollongong

  • Ehrenreich B, Dowie M, Minkin S (1979) The charge: gynocide; the accused: the US government. Mother Jones, Nov. http://www.motherjones.com/politics/1979/11/charge-gynocide. 9 Aug 2015

  • Engster D (2010) The place of parenting within a liberal theory of justice: the private parenting model, parental licenses, or public parenting support? Soc Theory Pract 36(2):233–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flavin J, Paltrow L (2010) Punishing pregnant drug-using women: defying law, medicine, and common sense. J Addict Dis 29(2):231–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman M (1997) The moral status of children: essays on the rights of children. Kluwer Law International, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuegen K, Biernat M, Haines E et al (2004) Mothers and fathers in the workplace: how gender and parental status influence judgments of job-related competence. J Soc Issues 60(4):737–754

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner M (2015) Beneficence and procreation. Philos Stud. doi:10.1007/s11098-015-0494-1

    Google Scholar 

  • Glasier A (2010) Acceptability of contraception for men: a review. Contraception 82(5):453–456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glasier A, Anakwe R, Everington D et al (2000) Would women trust their partners to use a male pill? Hum Reprod 15(3):646–649

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guttmacher Institute (2015) Refusing to provide health services. In: State policies in brief. http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/spib_RPHS.pdf. 1 Apr 2015

  • Hardon A (1994) The development of contraceptive technologies: a feminist critique. Gend Dev 2(2):40–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman E (2004) Can we harm and benefit in creating? Philos Perspect 18(1):89–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinemann K, Saad F, Wiesemes M et al (2005) Attitudes toward male fertility control: results of a multinational survey on four continents. Hum Reprod 20(2):549–556

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoggart L, Newton V (2013) Young women’s experiences of side-effects from contraceptive implants: a challenge to bodily control. Reprod Health Matters 21(41):196–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Human Rights Watch (2012) Sex workers at risk: condoms as evidence of prostitution in four US cities. In: Sex workers at risk. http://www.hrw.org/reports/2012/07/19/sex-workers-risk-0. 9 Feb 2015

  • Jha MK, Majmudar BC, Gorea A (2015) Responsibility for deaths of mothers in sterilization camps. Int J Eth Trauma Victimol 1(1):44–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler P, Manhart L, Lafferty W (2008) Abstinence-only and comprehensive sex education and the initiation of sexual activity and teen pregnancy. J Adolesc Health 42(4):344–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence J (2000) The Indian health service and the sterilization of Native American women. Am Indian Quart 24(3):400–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindemann H (2006) Bioethics’ gender. Am J Bioeth 6(2):W15–W19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucke J, Hall W (2012) Under what conditions is it ethical to offer incentives to encourage drug-using women to use long-acting forms of contraception? Addiction 107(6):1036–1041

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macklin R (1996) Cultural differences in long-acting contraception. In: Moskowitz E, Jennings B (eds) Coerced contraception: moral and policy challenges of long-acting birth control. Georgetown, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin C, Anderson R, Cheng L et al (2000) Potential impact of hormonal male contraception: cross-cultural implications for development of novel preparations. Hum Reprod 15:637–645

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2009) Asymmetries in the morality of causing people to exist. In: Roberts M, Wasserman D (eds) Harming future persons. Springer, Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills C (1999) The ethics of reproductive control. Philos Forum 30(1):43–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreau C, Cleland K, Trussell J (2007) Contraceptive discontinuation attributed to method dissatisfaction in the United States. Contraception 76(4):267–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mruk D (2008) New perspectives in non-hormonal male contraception. Trends Endocrinol Metab 19(2):57–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddens B (1999) Women’s satisfaction with birth control: a population survey of physical and psychological effects of oral contraceptives, intrauterine devices, condoms, natural family planning, and sterilization among 1466 women. Contraception 59(5):277–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oudshoorn N (2003) The male pill: a biography of a technology in the making. Duke, Durham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oudshoorn N (2004) Astronauts in the sperm world: the renegotiation of masculine identities in discourses on male contraceptives. Men Masc 6(4):349–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Page S, Amory J, Bremner W (2008) Advances in male contraception. Endocr Rev 29(4):465–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasulka N (2012) European countries force transgender sterilization. Mother Jones, Feb 16. http://www.motherjones.com/mojo/2012/02/most-european-countries-force-sterilization-transgender-people-map

  • Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act (2010) 42 U.S.C. § 18001

  • Pinkerton S (2001) A relative risk-based, disease-specific definition of sexual abstinence failure rates. Health Educ Behav 28(1):10–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Planned Parenthood (2014) Birth control methods. In: Birth control options. http://www.plannedparenthood.org/learn/birth-control. 25 Apr 2015

  • Purdy L (1996) Reproducing persons: issues in feminist bioethics. Cornell, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisner S, Perkovich B, Mimiaga M (2010) A mixed methods study of the sexual health needs of New England transmen who have sex with nontransgender men. Aids Patient Care STDs 24(8):501–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richie C (2013) Voluntary sterilization for childfree women. Hastings Cent Rep 43(6):36–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts D (1997) Killing the black body. Pantheon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson J (1996) Norplant and irresponsible reproduction. In: Moskowitz E, Jennings B (eds) Coerced contraception: moral and policy challenges of long-acting birth control. Georgetown, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Santelli J, Ott M, Lyon M et al (2006) Abstinence and abstinence-only education: a review of US policies and programs. J Adolesc Health 38(1):72–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz B, Gaventa S, Broome C, et al (1989) Nonmenstrual toxic shock syndrome associated with barrier contraceptives: report of a case-control study [with discussion]. Rev Infect Dis S43–S49

  • Shiffrin S (1999) Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Leg Theory 5(2):117–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock B (1996) The concept of coercion and long-term contraceptives. In: Moskowitz E, Jennings B (eds) Coerced contraception: moral and policy challenges of long-acting birth control. Georgetown, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Takeshita C (2012) The global biopolitics of the IUD: how science constructs contraceptive users and women’s bodies. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Terry G, Braun V (2011) ‘It’s kind of me taking responsibility for these things’: men, vasectomy and ‘contraceptive economies’. Fem Psychol 21(4):477–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trussell J (2004) Contraceptive failure in the United States. Contraception 70(2):89–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trussell J, Ellertson C, Stewart F et al (2004) The role of emergency contraception. Am J Obstet Gynecol 190(4):S30–S38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Kammen J, Oudshoorn N (2002) Gender and risk assessment in contraceptive technologies. Soc Health Illn 24(4):361–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warwick D (1975) Contraceptives in the third world. Hastings Cent Rep 5(4):9–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weston G, Schlipalius M, Bhuinneain M et al (2002) Will Australian men use male hormonal contraception? a survey of a postpartum population. Med J Aust 176(5):208–210

    Google Scholar 

  • Young T (2001) Overconsumption and procreation: are they morally equivalent? J Appl Philos 18(2):183–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Allen Wood, Sandra Shapshay, Kirk Ludwig, Noralyn Masselink, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emmalon Davis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Davis, E. What is it to Share Contraceptive Responsibility?. Topoi 36, 489–499 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9342-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9342-3

Keywords

Navigation