Skip to main content
Log in

Higher-Order Beliefs and the Undermining Problem for Bayesianism

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Jonathan Weisberg has argued that Bayesianism’s rigid updating rules make Bayesian updating incompatible with undermining defeat. In this paper, I argue that when we attend to the higher-order beliefs we must ascribe to agents in the kinds of cases Weisberg considers, the problem he raises disappears. Once we acknowledge the importance of higher-order beliefs to the undermining story, we are led to a different understanding of how these cases arise. And on this different understanding of things, the rigid nature of Bayesianism’s updating rules is no obstacle to its accommodating undermining defeat.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that what goes by the name “undermining defeat” in Weisberg’s discussion is more commonly referred to as “undercutting defeat”. For the canonical account of undercutting defeat, see Pollock (1986, 2008).

  2. The worry he raises is an extension of the argument from Weisberg (2009). The bulk of my discussion will focus on Weisberg (2015), where Weisberg attempts to sharpen this worry. However, we will return to consider some of the more general issues raised in Weisberg (2009) in Section 5.

  3. And where we assume that p(B) > 0.

  4. The correct philosophical interpretation of Jeffrey conditionalization is a complicated matter, made all the more complicated by the difference in how Jeffrey understood his own updating rule, and how others have appropriated it (and made more complicated still by the fact that Jeffrey’s own views about his updating rule were only clarified over time (cf. Jeffrey (1965) and Jeffrey(1983)). I follow Weisberg (and others) in understanding Jeffrey conditionalization as a substantive diachronic updating norm. See Weisberg (2015), 124.

  5. It was Jeffrey himself who first coined this term. See Jeffrey (1965).

  6. To avoid this cumbersome expression, in what follows, I will simply use the term “conditional probabilities” to denote those conditional probabilities that are conditional on the elements of the evidence partition. Where I do not have this more restricted usage in mind, context should make that clear.

  7. Weisberg (2015), 125.

  8. Weisberg (2015), 126. For the proof of this, see fn. 4 in the same.

  9. Weisberg (2015), 141. Note that I have replaced E′ with AB in this passage, as well as in the passages that follow.

  10. Weisberg (2015), 140–141.

  11. Weisberg (2015), 141.

  12. In other words, F∧HO slots into Y in the schema from Section 3:

    $$ p\left(\mathrm{X}\ |\ Y\right)=p\left(\mathrm{X}\right) $$
    $$ {p}^{\prime}\left(\mathrm{X}\ |\ Y\right)<{p}^{\prime}\left(\mathrm{X}\right) $$
  13. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this objection.

  14. Note that the above inequalities are not sufficient to establish that rigidity holds in the case at hand. In order to establish that rigidity holds, it must be shown that an agent who maintains these inequalities at t and t′ maintains them in virtue of the fact that they govern the same conditional probabilities at t and t′. In other words, in order to establish that rigidity holds, it must be shown that: p(E | F∧RAB) = p′(E | F∧RAB) and p(E | RAB) = p′(E | RAB).

    The intuitions I have appealed to in the argument above do indeed establish these equalities. I have argued that since the agent’s higher-order beliefs screen off (i.e., make probabilistically irrelevant) the impact of the experience in question in these cases, there is nothing that differentiates the agent’s conditional probabilities at t from her conditional probabilities at t′. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing out to me the need to establish this point.

  15. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me to address the following issues.

  16. See Jeffrey (1965, 1988, 2002). See also Wagner (2013) for how this observation bears on Weisberg’s discussion.

  17. For discussion of information minimization rules, see, for instance, Williams (1980), van Frasssen (1981) and Diaconis and Zabell (1982, p. 827–828). Some have resisted the idea that Jeffrey conditionalization should be associated with rigidity and contrasted with information minimization techniques. Diaconis and Zabell (1982, p. 827–828) argue that rigidity and information minimization measures are actually two ways of justifying Jeffrey Conditionalization. Along similar lines, Wagner (2013, n.5) insists that different strategies for requantifying a probability distribution all formally qualify as Jeffrey conditionalization. Wagner takes the difference between rigidity and other means of updating to be in the amount of ‘labor’ they employ.

  18. There are rules, other than information minimization rules, that also clearly classify as forms of Bayesian updating (see, for instance, Bradley (2005)). The general response offered in this section to the use of information minimization rules applies to these other rules as well.

  19. There is not much discussion in the literature on the connection between the choice of updating rule and the complexity of an agent’s evidence. Nevertheless, it seems reasonable to assume, as many have, that different updating rules (or justifications) will be appropriate for dealing with different types of evidence. For instance, Diaconis and Zabell (1982, p.827) take the labor employed by rigidity to be “subjective” and to involve “introspection”, since updating in this way requires identifying one’s evidence before and after an update. One might hypothesize that this sort of labor is most appropriate for cases involving simple, two-membered partitions—partitions that the agent can easily introspect as her evidence—than for cases that involve more complicated evidence.

  20. Weisberg (2015, p. 147) also makes this point. For discussion of the general strategy of updating on a more complicated evidence partition, see Wagner (2013).

  21. Sturgeon (2014), 117.

  22. Sturgeon (2014), 117.

  23. For a description of the Judy Benjamin problem, see again van Frasssen (1981).

  24. For a recent account of this, see Schwan and Stern (2017).

  25. Weisberg (2009), 5.

  26. Weisberg (2009), 1.

  27. Since undermining defeat is simply an instance of Jeffrey conditionalization, and Jeffrey conditionalization entails Holism (general) and is compatible with Holism (Weisberg), undermining defeat entails Holism (general) and is compatible with Holism (Weisberg).

  28. Weisberg (2009).

  29. Weisberg (2015), 122.

  30. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this comparison, and for prompting me to address the issues in this section.

  31. Carnap wrote this in a correspondence with Jeffrey, which is reprinted in Jeffrey (1975).

References

  • Bradley, R. (2005). Probability kinematics and Bayesian conditioning. Philosophy of Science, 72, 342–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1992). Confirmation holism and Bayesian epistemology. Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 540–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P., & Zabell, S. L. (1982). Updating subjective probability. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 77(380), 822–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1978). A note on Jeffrey conditionalization. Philosophy of Science, 45, 361–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1965). The logic of decision. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1975). Carnap’s empiricism. In G. Maxwell & R. M. Anderson Jr. (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. 6, Induction, Probability, and Confirmation (pp. 37–49). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1983). Bayesianism with a human face. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories (pp. 133–156). University of Minnesota Press.

  • Jeffrey, R. (1988). Conditioning, kinematics, and exchangeability. In B. Skyrms & W. Harper (Eds.), Causation, chance, and credence (Vol. 1). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (2002). Subjective probability: the real thing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (2008). Defeasible reasoning. In J. E. Adler & L. J. Rips (Eds.), Reasoning: studies of human inference and its foundations (pp. 451–470). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schwan, B., & Stern, R. (2017). A causal understanding of when and when not to Jeffrey conditionalize. Philosopher’s Imprint, 17.

  • Sturgeon, S. (2014). Pollock on defeasible reasons. Philosophical Studies, 169(1), 105–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Frasssen, B. C. (1981). A problem for relative information minimizers in probability kinematics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 32(4), 375–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, C. (2013). Is conditioning really incompatible with holism? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2), 409–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2009). Commutativity or holism? A dilemma for conditionalizers. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 793–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2015). Updating, undermining and independence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, 121–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, P. M. (1980). Bayesian conditionalization and the principle of minimum information. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 31, 131–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to several anonymous referees for very helpful comments and suggestions. I am especially grateful to Chris Meacham for extensive discussion and detailed written comments on multiple earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lisa Cassell.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest Statement

On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cassell, L. Higher-Order Beliefs and the Undermining Problem for Bayesianism. Acta Anal 34, 197–213 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0366-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0366-3

Keywords

Navigation