Skip to main content
Log in

Nietzsche’s Psychology of the Self: the Art of Overcoming the Divided Self

  • Arena of Identity
  • Published:
Human Arenas Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Nietzsche’s early to middle works, he has some interesting things to say about the psychology of the self. Indeed, Nietzsche explores the psychological consequences of the self that consists of a synthesis of competing opposites that are in a constant of flux. In order to make sense of the self, Nietzsche draws from the Hellenistic tradition of philosophy to conceptualise a therapeutic art of self-cultivation (Bildung) where the individual’s life is their work of art because every work of art is first turned toward the self and then toward others. This is why Nietzsche develops a mode of self-cultivation that is intimately connected with the painful labour of self-analysis in the hope of the self’s overcoming (Übergang); however, this is not enough by itself because it requires an understanding of the unconscious self that we have suppressed and repressed from ourselves, as well as the psychopathologies that they give rise to. To Nietzsche, the reason why we must undertake this difficult task of self-cultivation is the realisation that we need to free ourselves of narcissism, and its pathological symptoms found within the self, particularly if we are going to achieve a temperate and mature ego that is healthy for both the self and others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For some interesting examples of literature that deals with Nietzsche’s psychology, see the following: Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist (Kaufmann 1974), Composing the Soul (Parkes 1994), The Dionysian Self (Bishop 1995), Nietzsche’s Presence in Freud’s Life and Thought (Lehrer 1995), Nietzsche and Jung (Huskinson 2004), and Nietzsche’s Therapy (Ure 2008).

  2. From here on in, I will follow the academic convention of citing Nietzsche’s work using the initials of the English titles in the translations referred to in the reference section of this essay along with Arabic numerals to identify the volume, relevant part and numbered section or part, in this order (not page numbers). For details relating to the abbreviations and translations used, see the abbreviation and reference section. When required, I have referred to the original German translation of Nietzsche’s Werke from the Kritische Studienausgabe edited by Colli and Montinari that is published by Walter de Gruyter. In relation to the citation (i.e. BGE, §62), it is worth noting the German text, which states: “… der Mensch das noch nicht festgestellte Thier ist …”, particularly the terms “nicht festgestellte” which means “not firmly established”.

  3. In relation to the citation (i.e. HAH, I, §57), it is worth noting the German text, which states: “In der Moral behandelt sich der Mensch nicht als individuum, sondern als dividuum.” In this case, a narrow translation into English fails to account for Nietzsche’s focus on the way values consciously or unconsciously influence the way we act, and in a sense, provide an insight into our character, or who we are as individuals (our true self). When viewed in this context, reference to the ‘divided self’ is highly apt.

  4. The new preface to the reissued edition of BT, titled ‘Attempt at a Self-criticism’ was published in 1886. Here on in it will be cited as ‘BT, S-C’.

  5. Soll (1986, 1988, 1998) quite rightly questions whether Nietzsche’s view of life should be called ‘pessimistic’ because he changed and nuanced Schopenhauer’s pessimism into something of positive value by developing his own pessimism of the strong which rejects the view that life has no value and should be avoided as much as possible.

  6. Unfortunately, it has become de rigour in the psychoanalytic tradition to depict Nietzsche as a narcissist and/or associate his psychological insights with narcissism. Certainly, Freud’s ambivalence toward Nietzsche has certainly contributed to this view; however, recent work by Parkes (1994) has demonstrated the significant contribution Nietzsche makes to analytical psychology. It is worth noting Nietzsche’s prophetic words in EC (EC, ‘Why I am A Destiny’, §6), when he states: “Who before me at all among philosophers has been a psychologist and not rather its opposite ‘higher swindler’, ‘idealist’? Before me there was no psychology. To be the first here can be a curse, it is in any case a destiny: for one is also the first to despiseDisgust at mankind is my danger …”.

  7. To Nietzsche, the idea of ‘free will’ is a myth, and hence why he states that in ‘… real life it is only a question of strong and weak wills’ (BGE, §21).

  8. Neither the concepts of the ‘will to power’, nor the ‘Übermensch’ are part of Nietzsche’s thinking at this juncture in BT as they are developed in subsequent works. See the section titled, ‘The will to power as art’ in WP §794–853 it is worth noting that Nietzsche classes ‘beauty’ as a ‘biological value’ because it is known to all human beings and yet taken for granted until we are reminded of ‘ugliness’. This is why beauty is a ‘biological value’ because it serves a life sustaining need, in the same way as air, water, food and so on.

  9. In The Republic (Book X), Plato argues that art imitates physical objects, which in turn imitates the Forms. In other words, art is a ‘copy of a copy’ of a Form and best viewed as an ‘illusion’ and something not ‘real’.

  10. See WP: the reference to ‘illness’ as a ‘great stimulant’ to life is taken from §1003, the ‘biological value of the beautiful and the ugly’ is taken from §804, and the condition of the artist is taken from §811.

  11. Nietzsche’s work titled, On the Future of Educational Institutions provides a useful starting place to some of his earliest thoughts on the concept of Bildung, particularly why he was concerned with the concept, and how he thinks it can be cultivated as an ethics of character. To Nietzsche, the strong emphasis on Bildung is consistent with his ethics of character because each are concerned with the notion of striving to become better human beings by overcoming the old self through the ‘revaluation of all values’ in order to affirm ancient Greek values considered valuable to a person’s character, such as courage, wisdom, justice, honesty, temperance, and so on. See for example, the following: ‘Nietzsche on aesthetics, educators and education’ (Stolz 2017), ‘A genealogical analysis of the concept of ‘good’ teaching: A polemic’ (Stolz 2018), and ‘Nietzsche: truth, perspectivism, and his concern with Bildung’ (Stolz 2019).

  12. It is worth noting that even though Freud denied having read Nietzsche’s work, there is persuasive evidence that he was both directly and indirectly familiar with his general corpus. Interestingly, Freud (1914/1917) does acknowledge and concede that Nietzsche ‘anticipated’ his central themes, and in many instances psychoanalysis confirms his psychology. See, The History of the Psychoanalytic Movement.

  13. See Charmides from Plato’s dialogues. The two Delphic commands being: ‘know thyself’ and ‘nothing in excess’.

References

  • Bishop, P. (1995). The Dionysian self: C. G. Jung’s reception of Friedrich Nietzsche. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1914/1917). The history of the psychoanalytic movement. New York: The Nervous and Mental Disease Publishing Company (original work published 1914).

  • Huskinson, L. (2004). Nietzsche and Jung: the whole self in the union of opposites. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, W. (1974). nietzsche: philosopher, psychologist, antichrist (4th edn.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Lehrer, R. (1995). Nietzsche’s presence in Freud’s life and thought: on the origins of a psychology of dynamic unconscious mental functioning. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1872/2006). On the future of our educational institutions [Über die Zukunft unserer Bildungsanstalten]. Translation by D. Searls and Introduction by P. Reitter and C. Wellmon. New York, NY: New York Review Books (series of 5 lectures held in Basel between January and March 1972 which form part of Nietzsche’s Nachlass, but unpublished).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1874/1997). Third Part: Schopenhauer as Educator [Drittes Stück: Schopenhauer als Erziher]. In D. Breazeale (Ed.), Untimely meditations [Unzeitmässe Betrachtungen]. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale (pp. 125–194). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (original work published 1874).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1878/1996). Human, all too human: A book for free spirits: Volume I and II [Menschliches, Allzumenschliches: Ein Bucg für freie Geister]. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale and introduction by R. Schacht. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (original work published 1878).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1881/1997). Daybreak: thoughts on the prejudices of morality [Morgenröte: Gedanken über die moralischen Vorurteile]. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (original work published 1881).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1882/1974). The gay science: With a prelude in rhymes and an appendix of songs [die fröhliche Wissencraft: Scherz, list und Rache und lieder des Prinzen Vogelfrei] translated by W. Kaufmann. New York, NY: Vintage Press (original work published 1882).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1883–1892/1961). Thus spoke Zarathustra: a book for everyone and no one [also sprach Zarathustra: Ein Buch für Alle und Keinen] translation and introduction by R. J. Hollingdale. London, UK: Penguin Books (Part I and II were published 1883, Part III in 1884, Part IV was published in 1885 and distributed among friends, and the first public distribution of Part IV was in 1892).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1886/1973). Beyond good and evil: prelude to a philosophy of the future [Jensuits von gut and Böse: Vorspiel einer Philosophie der Zunkunft] translated by R. J. Hollingdale and introduction by M. Tanner. London, UK: Penguin Books (original work published 1886).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1887/1998). On the genealogy of morality: a polemic [Zur Genealogie der moral: Eine Streitschrift]. Translated and Introduction by M. Clark and A. J. Swensen. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing (original work published 1887).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1889/2014). Twilight of the idols: how to philosophise with a hammer [Götzen-Dämmerung: Wie man mit dem hammer philosophiert]. Translated by W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. Luxemourg: CreateSpace Independent Publishers (original work published 1889).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1895a/2005). The antichrist [Der Antichrist] (trans: H. L. Mencken). New York, NY: Cosimo Classics (original work published 1895).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1895b/2005). Nietzsche Contra Wagner: a psychologist’s brief [Nietzsche contra Wagner: Aktenstücke eines Psychologen]. (trans: Ludovici, A.). New York, NY: Pantianos Classics (original work publically published 1895).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1908/1979). Ecce Homo: How one becomes what one is [ecce Homo: Wie man wird, was man ist]. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale and introduction by M. Tanner. London, UK: Penguin Books (original work published 1908).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1873/1962). Philosophy in the tragic age of the greeks. Translated by M. Cowan. Chicago, IL: Regnery gateway (part of Nietzsche’s Nachlass that was written in 1873, but unpublished).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1967). The will to power [Der Wille zur Macht]. Translated by W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale and commentary by W. Kaufmann. New York, NY: Vintage Books (part of Nietzsche’s Nachlass that was written between 1883–1888, and posthumously published).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1873/1979). Philosophy in hard times [Die Philosophie in Bedrängriss]. In D. Breazeale (Ed.), Philosophy and Truth [Philosophie und Wahrheit]: Selections from Nietzsche’s notebooks of the early 1870s. Translated by D. Breazeale (pp. 101–123). New Jersey, NJ: Humanities Press (part of Nietzsche’s Nachlass that was written in 1873, but unpublished).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1872/1993). The birth of tragedy: out of the spirit of music [die Geburt der Tragödie: Aus dem Gesite de Musik]. Translated by S. Whiteside and introduction by M. Tanner. London: Penguin Books (original work published 1872).

  • Nietzsche, F. (1874/1997). Second part: on the uses and disadvantages of history for life [Zweites Stück: Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für das Leben]. In D. Breazeale (Ed.), Untimely meditations [Unzeitmässe Betrachtungen]. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale (pp. 57–123). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press (original work published 1874).

  • Parkes, G. (1994). Composing the soul: Reaches of Nietzsche’s psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1961). Charmides. In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), Plato: the collected dialogue (pp. 99–122). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soll, I. (1986). The hopelessness of hedonism and the will to power. International Studies in Philosophy, 18, 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soll, I. (1988). Pessimism and the tragic view of life: reconsiderations of Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy. In R. Solomon & K. Higgins (Eds.), Reading Nietzsche (pp. 104–131). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soll, I. (1998). Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and redemption of life through art. In C. Janaway (Ed.), Willing and nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s educator (pp. 79–115). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soll, I. (2001). Nietzsche on the illusions of everyday experience. In R. Schacht (Ed.), Nietzsche’s postmoralism: essays on Nietzsche’s prelude to philosophy’s future (pp. 7–33). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolz, S. A. (2017). Nietzsche on aesthetics, educators and education. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 36(6), 683–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stolz, S. A. (2018). A genealogical analysis of the concept of ‘good’ teaching: a polemic. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 52(1), 144–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stolz, S. A. (2019). Nietzsche: truth, perspectivism, and his concern with Bildung. Manuscript submitted for publication.

  • Ure, M. (2008). Nietzsche’s therapy. Plymouth: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven A. Stolz.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stolz, S.A. Nietzsche’s Psychology of the Self: the Art of Overcoming the Divided Self. Hu Arenas 3, 264–278 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-019-00081-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-019-00081-x

Keywords

Navigation