Skip to main content

The Dynamic Block Universe and the Illusion of Passage

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Illusions of Time

Abstract

The passage of time seems to be a fundamental aspect of experience. However, most descriptions of the passage of time itself are incompatible with the four-dimensional block universe model of space and time, in which time is extended like space, and all states of affairs exist equally and eternally in this varied tapestry of space and time. The tension between temporal passage and the block universe seems to leave one with the option of either abandoning the block universe in favor of a metaphysics that can accommodate our experience, or holding that this experience of passage is illusory. I argue for a third option: (a) that we have certain dynamic experiences, which lend themselves to the view that time passes, (b) those dynamic experiences can be accounted for within the block universe model without any additional mechanism, and (c) those dynamic experiences are not illusory, but veridical.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Many have argued that genuine change does not merely involve being in a different state at different times, for that would only give you temporal variation. Rather, genuine change must involve some change in the state of affair itself, namely a change in its presentness. See McTaggart, J. E. M. (1908). The Unreality of Time. Mind, 17(68), 457–474.

  2. 2.

    Most famously, C.D. Broad considers this the spotlight of the present.

  3. 3.

    Paul (2010) uses the phrase “as of” to indicate that there is no object of experience that could be identified as passage.

  4. 4.

    Insofar as Deng and Hoerl argue that there is no phenomenology of passage of the type described in A-theoretic terms, they are not at odds with Huggett with respect to this point.

  5. 5.

    Daniel Dennett (2003) uses this quote by Lee Siegel to make a similar point regarding consciousness.

  6. 6.

    Although I have drawn on this analogy with magic, I still resist the idea that the world is producing in us illusions of temporal passage. In the case of the magic trick, there is a disconnect between what the magician has made you perceive and the reality of the situation—the magician is trying to deceive you—and importantly, the magician can only deceive you by taking advantage of the perceptual mechanisms that usually work very well in accurately tracking the way the world is.

  7. 7.

    Specifically, they refer to the phi-phenomenon; however, this term has since been shown to be misapplied in this case, although “color-phi” is still typically (and in this paper) used despite the misnomer. See Steinman, Pizlo, and Pizlo (2000) for a more thorough discussion.

  8. 8.

    The Orwellian account is not entirely at odds with the view of temporal representation whereby time is not its own representation. Rather, the problematic aspect of the Orwellian account comes from its denial that the “rewritten history” is part of conscious experience and its placement of the rewrite into memory instead.

  9. 9.

    While still working with signals only indicating changes in illumination, in primates, A and B are actually intermediate neurons gathering information from groups of photoreceptors rather than individual receptors.

  10. 10.

    Traditionally, there is thought to be two distinct systems involved in processing motion, short range and long range. Cavanagh and Mather, however, argue that experimental evidence points to there being a single system, but with lower and higher orders of processing, depending on the stage of the processing and the information being integrated (Cavanagh & Mather, 1989).

  11. 11.

    Wertheimer calls this “pure” motion, which is produced when the flashes are timed sufficiently close together. See Steinman et al. (2000).

  12. 12.

    No doubt, by “appropriate” Paul means sufficiently close in space and time (up to 4 degrees of visual angle and up to about half a second apart), but the lower end of this spectrum would limit zero.

  13. 13.

    A thorough and closely related discussion of our experience of passage and our experience of objects as enduring is taken up more fully in Prosser (2012), Deng (2013), and Hoerl (2014).

  14. 14.

    In his paper, Prosser argues that, in our experiences of motion and change, we represent the objects undergoing such change as enduring, an A-theoretic form of persistence. This, in itself, is a rich topic that requires a much fuller treatment than can be done here, so this passage is only being used to discuss what a plausible description of a veridical experience of B-theoretic change might look like.

  15. 15.

    One may object that akinetopic experience importantly lacks the intermediary positions of the objects; the experience has gaps where there are none in the world. The absence of the intermediary positions in experience ought not be too troubling, though, since an anti-illusionist would concede that I can certainly experience, for instance, the real motion of an animal as it runs behind a slatted fence, obscuring its intermediary positions.

References

  • Cavanagh, P., & Mather, G. (1989). Motion: The long and short of it. Spatial Vision, 4(2/3), 103–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deng, N. (2013). On explaining why time seems to pass. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51(3), 367–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2003). Explaining the “magic” of consciousness. Journal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology, 1(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D., & Kinsbourne, M. (1992). Time and the observer. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2014). Do we (seem to) perceive passage? Philosophical Explorations, 17(2), 188–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2014). Skeptical notes on a physics of passage. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1326(1), 9–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather, G. (2006a). Foundations of perception. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mather, G. W. (2006b). Motion perception, psychology of. In L. Nadel (Ed.), Encyclopedia of cognitive science. John Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/0470018860.s00581

  • McTaggart, J. E. M. (1908). The unreality of time. Mind, 17(68), 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2010). Temporal experience. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 333–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1998). Some free thinking about time. In P. van Inwagen & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Metaphysics: The big questions (pp. 104–107). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prosser, S. (2012). Why does time seem to pass? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(1), 92–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegal, L. (1991). Net of magic: Wonders and deceptions in India. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinman, R. M., Pizlo, Z., & Pizlo, F. J. (2000). Phi is not beta, and why Weirtheimer’s discovery launched the gestalt revolution. Vision Research, 40, 2257–2264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zihl, J., Von Cramon, D., & Mai, N. (1983). Selective disturbance of movement vision after bilateral brain damage. Brain, 106, 313–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Balcells .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Balcells, M. (2019). The Dynamic Block Universe and the Illusion of Passage. In: Arstila, V., Bardon, A., Power, S.E., Vatakis, A. (eds) The Illusions of Time. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22048-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics