Skip to main content

Why We Do Not Perceive Aesthetic Properties

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mind, Values, and Metaphysics

Abstract

This chapter examines whether there are genuine cases of aesthetic perception, and hence whether aesthetic judgements depend on the perception of aesthetic properties. My response will be negative. Specifically, I will argue that although our access to aesthetic ‘properties’ does appear to resemble perception in certain respects, it differs in two key ways from cases of ordinary everyday perception: (a) in its opacity (i.e. its lacking transparency) and (b) in its partly nonattributive phenomenology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Perhaps also we can also sometimes see just that something is aesthetically good, without knowing in virtue of what. Such cases complicate matters and fall beyond the scope of the present discussion, though see the view of Sibley discussed below.

  2. 2.

    See for example Scruton (2007) for a sceptical view about the capacity of tastes and smells to be of aesthetic value. For the contrary view see Sibley (2001, Chap. 15).

  3. 3.

    Although strong intentionalism does not strictly speaking require transparency (Byrne 2001), its proponents argue that it is best placed to account for it, so any reasons for doubting the transparency of perceptual experience are at least prima facie reasons to doubt the plausibility of the view. See also Speaks (2010).

  4. 4.

    The difficulty is multiplied when the possibility of cognitive penetration is taken into account.

  5. 5.

    I intend the phenomenology of the experience to be understood very broadly, encompassing cognitive reflection on the nature of our experiences, and on the nature of their relation to the world.

References

  • Block N (2010) Attention and mental paint. Philos Issues 20:23–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (2001) Intentionalism defended. Philos Rev 110:199–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins R (2010) Inflected pictorial experience: its treatment and significance. In: Abell C, Batinaki K (eds) Philosophical perspectives on picturing. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind A (2003) What’s so transparent about transparency. Philos Stud 115:225–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacPherson F (2006) Ambiguous figures and the content of experience. Noûs 40:82–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn C (2004) Mindsight: image, dream, meaning. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay B (2010) Attention and perceptual content. Analysis 70:263–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts R (2003) Emotions: an essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scruton R (1974) Art and imagination. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton R (2007) The philosophy of wine. In: Smith B (ed) Questions of taste. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Sibley F (2001) Approach to aesthetics: collected papers on philosophical aesthetics (Benson J, Redfern B, Cox J (eds)). Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel S (2012) Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Noûs 46:201–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Speaks J (2010) Attention and intentionalism. Philos Q 60:325–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (2008) The experience of emotion: an intentionalist theory. Rev Int Philos 243:25–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton K (2004) Categories of art. In: Lamarque P, Olsen SH (eds) Aesthetics and the philosophy of art: the analytic tradition: an anthology. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 142–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Watzl S (2011) Attention as structuring of the stream of consciousness. In: Mole C, Smithies D, Wu W (eds) Attention: philosophical and psychological essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 145–173

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This chapter was completed while on research leave funded by the Swiss National Science Foundation. In addition to them, I would like to thank Kevin Mulligan for his always lucid, illuminating, and provocative comments in many discussions on many topics, including the one presented here. I would also like to thank Anne Reboul for her tireless work on this collection.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cain Todd .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Todd, C. (2014). Why We Do Not Perceive Aesthetic Properties. In: Reboul, A. (eds) Mind, Values, and Metaphysics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05146-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics