Skip to main content

Critical Theory of Human Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

Abstract

International human rights have become an important global norm that has increasingly been incorporated into international law and global conventions. Human rights are a key reference point of mobilizations by diverse groups and international nongovernmental organization (INGOs) in global publics and global civil society. And human rights are also often critically appropriated by domestic and transnational political struggles of political activists and dissidents. Yet human rights are also used and abused by regimes, global (legal, economic, and political) institutions, and powerful corporate interests stabilizing a profoundly injust global social order. Drawing from Frankfurt School theorizing and critically examining more recent discussions among theorists partly indebted to this tradition (Benhabib, Forst), this chapter reflects on contemporary human rights debates and their meaning for critical cosmopolitan theory and politics today. It is argued that contemporary critical theory offers an important lens to situate human rights in global and local social and material conditions while recognizing human rights as a tool in struggles for political freedom and global social justice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For instance, over 40 human rights and gay rights groups, including major international nongovernmental organizations (INGOs) such as Amnesty International, Human Rights Watch, and the Human Rights Campaign, supported the political struggle with an open letter to the ten world sponsors of the 2014 Winter Olympics hosted by Russia in Sochi in the prelude to the Games, “urging them to denounce the law and run ads promoting equality for lesbians, gays, bisexuals and transgender people” (cited in Crary 2013).

  2. 2.

    Exceptions are critical studies by Seyla Benhabib (2006, 2011) and Rainer Forst (2012), to which I will briefly turn later in this chapter.

  3. 3.

    For an initial overview on this reception and the relevance of Horkheimer for critical legal studies (CLS) see Cotterrell (1997) and, focusing on Franz Neumann and Otto Kirchheimer, who are not part of the “inner circle” of Frankfurt School theorizing, Scheuerman (1997).

  4. 4.

    See Marx (1975). On Marx and jurisprudence, see Fine (2002). Adorno sharpens his lens for the critique of rights in his own critical reading of Hegel’s philosophy of right. Offering an appropriate interpretation of Hegel or not, for Adorno Hegel betrays his philosophy of freedom but his degradation of individuals realistically reflects the reality of modern society’s development and the modern state’s actual indifference to the lives of individuals, which finds reflection in the indifference of law (Adorno 1966; Adorno 1964; Fine 2012: 165f). The false universal that Hegel glorifies, Adorno suggests, affirms a concept of the state in which the collective overwhelms the subjective rights of the individual Hegel also talks about. Ultimately, despising both individual freedom and free institutions, Hegel, in Adorno’s view, promotes blind obedience to the state organization by unreflectively selling the integration into the “objective legal norm” as rational and democratic (Adorno 1966: 345). Tolerating the particular only as a category, however, reduces the dialectic of legal norms and rights, which can both restrict and generate or protect freedom, into a “dialectics at a standstill” (Adorno 1966: 334; Rensmann 2016: 26–29).

  5. 5.

    It is noteworthy that Horkheimer and Adorno’s argument from the start also, if only cautiously, concedes that there may be a moment of freedom in the relative independence of law. As justice brooks no interference, law possibly provides a place of right against direct domination or political interference, that is: the rule of immediate power.

  6. 6.

    It is noteworthy that the Frankfurt School’s first major work addressing human rights, the Dialectic of Enlightenment, was written at a time when human rights had no international institutional grounding and was still largely limited to intellectual debates, philanthropy, or embedded in minority rights. Critical Theory’s initial treatment thus preceded the Nuremberg Trial, the Genocide Convention, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, and the Preamble of the United Nations Charter, which shortly thereafter gave universal human rights international legal status.

  7. 7.

    This critique is grounded in the critique of liberal political theory’s notion of negative freedom—in its classical version: Bentham—where the function of the law and the state is to secure that individual liberty, based in the axiom of liberal individualism, is infringed as little as possible. The liberal idea of negative freedom, or freedom from interference, leads to a minimalist definition of human rights as freedom from direct physical violence, leaving other fundamental questions of human (social) need as well as universal human freedom and democratic empowerment unaddressed. Adorno proposes (and justifies) a primacy of human solidarity that is based on a raw moral, if not “vulgar-Marxist” claim, namely that all poverty needs to be abolished: “There is tenderness only in the coarsest demand: that no-one shall go hungry any more” (Adorno 1974: 156). Ultimately, this is a claim all liberal theory seeks to evade. Of course, the cheated masses Horkheimer and Adorno talk about here in the context of a theory of fascism and antisemitism are especially the fascist masses which reject the liberal claim of human rights altogether in face of their lacking realization.

  8. 8.

    Indeed, Irr rightly argues that the “literalism of the rights discourse,” despite its appeal to political contestation, “testifies to the rise of Weberian technocracy, a structure that addresses inequality for the purpose of crisis management,” not inequality’s “principled eradication” (Irr 2012: 173). Yet it seems misguided to discern some sort of absolute negativity as an inevitable tendency toward “unlimited power … at any price” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: 138). There is no direct path to a “regression to absolute barbarism” (Irr 2012: 173), in the form of antisemitism, fascism, and the complete destruction of the rule of law and rights entitlements.

  9. 9.

    Adorno and Horkheimer unfold a critique of enlightenment reason without throwing the baby out with the bathwater, that is, destroying the critical element of enlightenment concepts such as freedom and reason, without which there can be no human emancipation; Critical Theory is the project, in the words of Stephen Eric Bronner, to self-reflexively reclaim the Enlightenment, not to abandon it or defame it. See Bronner (2004; Rensmann 2011: 5). As Adorno and Horkheimer argue: “The critique of enlightenment … is intended to prepare a positive concept of enlightenment which liberates it from its entanglement in blind domination.” Adorno, indeed, investigates the self-destruction of enlightenment in order to create self-awareness of this process and ultimately to rescue enlightenment. Adorno’s method is “determinate negation” with and beyond Hegel. It gives prominence to an element which “distinguishes enlightenment from the positivist decay to which [Hegel] consigned it.” “Enlightenment is totalitarian” only in so far as it “prejudges its trial,” that is, insofar that it becomes a closed system and turns its claims to autonomy into its opposite: an exclusively heteronomous logic (see Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: xviii, 18). Indeed, as James Schmidt aptly puts it, the relentless critics remain loyal to Enlightenment hopes (Schmidt 1998: 835).

  10. 10.

    While freedom is a product of history, Adorno preserves and defends the “permanent component” (Adorno 1964: 181) of the concept of freedom against the historical dialectical tradition of Hegel and Marx (Fine 2012: 164), that is: for Adorno freedom has always ties to individual human beings, in spite of all historical changes the meaning of freedom has undergone over time, and “concrete possibilities of freedom can be found at every moment in history … whenever individuality genuinely asserts itself” (Fine 2012: 164).

  11. 11.

    “For all their dyspeptic, and often careless, dismissal of political liberalism, Adorno and Horkheimer are political liberals in the sense clarified for us by John Rawls.” (Benhabib 2011: 38)

  12. 12.

    For a persuasive critique of Arendt’s Kantianism with regard to the antinomies of law from a perspective that invokes Adorno’s critique of the legal form and his materialistically grounded spirit of solidarity, see Reeves (2009).

  13. 13.

    Nazi and fascist ideologies aim at destroying Western legal norms, an early modern example of which is the Nazi ideologue Alfred Rosenberg (1923). While fascist and other authoritarian groups and regimes demonstrate until this day that human rights are not inalienable but indeed can be systematically and grossly violated, those who expose this contradiction in order to oppose human rights altogether as a farce are in sync with the blind fascist affect against right. Critical Theorists reject such indeterminate negation of law and human rights as a regression to naked particularism, collective and individual, that expresses an anti-Western, anti-Enlightenment ideology.

  14. 14.

    This profoundly distinguishes Critical Theory from poststructuralists like Butler (1992), who fail to understand the dialectics of rights and other critical concepts.

  15. 15.

    She also argues against liberal “interventionism” and “possessive individualism” (Benhabib 2011: 67).

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 1941. Letter to Max Horkheimer, October 2, 1941, Max Horkheimer Archive VI.32.29 (translated in Rolf Wiggershaus, The Frankfurt School, 309).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1962. Progress. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, ed. Adorno, 143–160. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964. History and freedom: Lectures 1964–1965. Cambridge: Polity Press . 2006 [1964–1965].

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. Negative dialectics. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969. Critique. In Critical models: interventions and catchwords, ed. Adorno, 281–288. New York: Columbia University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. Minima moralia: Reflections from damaged life. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2006. Another cosmopolitanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Claiming rights across borders: International human rights and democratic sovereignty. American Political Science Review 103(4): 691–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Dignity in adversity: Human rights in troubled times. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronner, Steven Eric. 2004. Reclaiming the enlightenment: Towards a politics of radical engagement. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Wendy. 2007. Edgework: Critical essays on knowledge and politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1992. Contingent foundations: Feminism and the question of postmodernism. In Feminists theorize the political, ed. Judith Butler, and Joan W. Scott. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Eric O. 2000. Virtuous vice: Homoeroticism and the public sphere. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cotterrell, Roger. 1997. Critique and law: The legacy of the Frankfurt School. In Law’s community: Legal theory in sociological perspective, ed. Roger Cotterrell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crary, David. 2013. Foes of Russia’s anti-gay laws consider new tactics. New York Daily News, November 17. http://www.nydailynews.com/news/world/groups-protest-russian-anti-gay-laws-article-1.1520015.

  • Ferrara, Alessandro. 2015. The democratic horizon: Hyperpluralism and the renewal of political liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Robert. 2002. Democracy and the rule of law: Marx’s critique of the legal form. Caldwell: The Blackburn Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Debating human rights, law, and subjectivity: Arendt, Adorno, and Critical Theory. In Arendt and Adorno: Political and Philosophical Investigations, ed. Lars Rensmann, and Samir Gandesha, 154–172. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Robert, and Will Smith. 2003. Jürgen Habermas’s theory of cosmopolitanism. Constellations 10(4): 469–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer. 2012. The right to justification: Elements of a constructivist theory of justice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frost, Meryva. 2002. Constituting human rights: Global civil society and the society of democratic states. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998a. On the internal relation between the rule of law and democracy. In The inclusion of the other: Studies in political theory, ed. Jürgen Habermas, Ciaran Cronin, and Pablo De Greiff, 253–264. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998b. Kant’s idea of perpetual peace: At two hundred years’ historical remove. In The inclusion of the other: Studies in political theory, ed. Jürgen Habermas, Ciaran Cronin, and Pablo De Greiff, 165–201. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Does the constitutionalization of international law still have a chance? In The divided west, ed. Jürgen Habermas, and Ciaran Cronin, 115–193. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of enlightenment: Philosophical fragments. Stanford: Stanford University Press . 2002 [1969].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ignatieff, Michael. 2000. Human rights as politics and idolatry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingram, David. 2010. Habermas: Introduction and analysis. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irr, Caren. 2012. One-dimensional symptoms: What Marcuse offers a critical theory of law. In Rethinking the Frankfurt School: Alternative legacies of cultural critique, ed. Jeffrey T. Nealon, and Caren Irr, 169–186. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis, Simon. 1998. Adorno: A critical introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, Mary. 1996. Cosmopolitanism versus nationalism: The new divide? In Europe’s new nationalism: States and minorities in conflict, ed. Richard Caplan and John Feffer, 42–58. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, Mary. 2007. Global civil society. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreide, Regina. 2016. Between morality and law: in defense of a political conception of human rights. Journal of International Political Theory 12(1): 10–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurth, James. 2005. Humanitarian intervention after the war in Iraq: Legal ideals vs. military realities. Orbis 50: 87–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1975. Contribution to a critique of Hegel’s philosophy of law. In Marx’s early writings, ed. Lucio Coletti. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rensmann, Lars. 2012. Grounding cosmopolitics: Rethinking crimes against humanity and global political theory with Arendt and Adorno. In Arendt and Adorno: Political and philosophical investigations, ed. Lars Rensmann, and Samir Gandesha, 129–153. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Back to Kant? The democratic deficits in Habermas’ global constitutionalism. In Deprovinicializing habermas: Global perspectives, ed. Tom Bailey, 27–49. New York/London/New Dehli: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Adorno and the global public sphere: Rethinking globalization and the cosmopolitan condition of politics. In Re-imagining public space: The Frankfurt School and beyond, ed. Diana Boros, and James M. Glass, 163–190. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Sports, global politics, and social value change: A research agenda. Altre Modernità 14(5): 114–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. National sovereigntism and global constitutionalism: An adornian cosmopolitan critique. Critical Horizons 17(1): 14–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeves, Craig. 2009. Exploding the limits of law: Judgment and freedom in Arendt and Adorno. Res Publica 15(2): 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, William E. 1997. Between the norm and exception: The Frankfurt School and the rule of law. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, William E. 2011. Frankfurt School perspectives on globalization, democracy, and the law. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, James. 1998. Language, mythology, and enlightenment: Historical notes on Horkheimer and Adorno’s ‘dialectic of enlightenment’. Social Research 65: 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, Judith N. 1964. Legalism: Law, morals, and political trials. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, Beth. 2009. Mobilizing for human rights. International law in domestic politics. New York/Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tsutsui, Kiyoteru, and Christine Min Wotipka. 2004. Global civil society and the international human rights movement: Citizen participation in human rights international nongovernmental organizations. Social Forces 83(2): 587–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1994. The Frankfurt School: Its history, theories, and political significance. Trans. M. Robertson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zolo, Danilo. 2004. The political and legal dilemmas of globalisation. Theoria 51(103): 28–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rensmann, L. (2017). Critical Theory of Human Rights. In: Thompson, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55801-5_29

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics