Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Vulnerability as a key concept in relational patient- centered professionalism

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The goal of this paper is to propose a relational turn in healthcare professionalism, to improve the responsiveness of both healthcare professionals and organizations towards care of patients, but also professionals. To this end, it is important to stress the way in which difficult situations and vulnerability faced by professionals can have an impact on their performance of work. This article pursue two objectives. First, I focus on understanding and making visible shared vulnerability that arises in clinical settings from a triple perspective: patient and family, health professionals, and institutions. Second, to address this challenge for professionalism, in this paper I articulate the term "relational centered-patient professionalism", which has two main axes. The relational approach means taking into account how the relationships among professionals, patients and institutions determine the constitution and evolution of those professional values. The focus on patient centered care is indispensable, because it is the ultimate goal pursued by the development of these professional values, and must always be at the center.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To follow in depth the publications related to the "Fifteenth Session of the International Bioethics Committee", see http://docplayer.net/19142085-Fifteenth-session-of-the-international-bioethics-committee-ibc-unesco-headquarters-paris-27-29-october-2008.html). The opening session was about "Principle of respect for human vulnerability and personal integrity: theoretical challenges and practical achievements" (http://www.unesco.org/new/fileadmin/MULTIMEDIA/HQ/SHS/pdf/Human-Vulnerability-Patrao-Neves.pdf.

  2. As ten Have (2016) states, there are a group of philosophical perspectives emphasizing that vulnerability is a general characteristic of being human, but usually these theories are not considered to be relevant for the practical discourse of bioethics. These philosophical perspectives on vulnerability do not advocate for a vulnerable subject against an autonomous subject, but argue that vulnerability is constitutive of personal autonomy, and due to that it is preferable to use the term "anthropological" rather than "ontological" vulnerability. I will refer to this conception as universal, anthropological or shared vulnerability.

  3. Ten Have explains why the term "ontological vulnerability" is not appropriate to express that vulnerability is the most characteristic of the human beings. Ontology states there is an essential reality prior to ethical discourse, which in the dominant bioethical discourse on the idea that the autonomous subject is prior to its context. However, philosophical perspectives on vulnerability shows that ethics and ontology cannot be separated. Those perspectives argue that vulnerability is constitutive of individual autonomy, and that autonomy can only emerge from a vulnerable subject. Vulnerability is the human condition, and autonomy a capacity that need to arise. For these reasons, ten Have propose to use the term "anthropological" rather than "ontological" vulnerability.

  4. https://web.gs.emory.edu/vulnerability/index.html. Last accessed 11/22/2020.

  5. For further details, visit the VHC Initiative’s website: https://web.gs.emory.edu/vulnerability/about/definitions.html (last visited 11\06\2020).

  6. For further details about these means, see Fineman (2015).

  7. In a systematic review about healthcare staff wellbeing, burnout and patient safety, Hall et al. (2016) found in the majority of studies reviewed poor wellbeing and burnout are associated with poor patient safety outcomes such as medical errors.

  8. This project was initiated by the American Board of Internal Medicine Foundation, the American College of Physicians Foundation, and the European Federation of Internal Medicine.

  9. The list of commitments includes: (a) commitment to professional competence, (b) to honesty with patients, (c) to patients’ confidentiality, (d) to maintaining appropriate relationships with patients, (e) to improving quality of care, (f) to improving access to care, (g) to a just distribution of finite resources, (h) to scientific knowledge, (i) to maintaining trust by managing conflicts of interest, and (j) to professional’s responsibilities.

  10. The proposal of Shapiro et al. (2015) is to promote the study of Literature as a way to learn in an emotionally and critically engaging way; to learn how individuals face moral dilemmas, solve them and the consequences of those resolutions. They understand literature to be an essential element of medical education: “literature can deepen the understanding of medical professionalism, as many medical educators desire” (pp. 6–7).

  11. Pellegrino (2012) maintains that medical ethics is primarily about caring for the good of the patients, which means each patient, and society as a whole, depends upon the physician’s formation of a good character, i.e., on the acquisition of the virtues that make for a good physician. He claims that virtue is an unavoidable element in any system of medical ethics.

  12. Pellegrino defines the good of the patient in tangible terms connected to the phenomenology of the clinical encounter. The good of the patients is explained as a quadripartite good, a complex relationship between medical, personal, human, and spiritual good. This concept creates the duties of the clinician. As he concludes, a theory of the good of the patient has applicability for the ethics of the other healing and helping professions and the virtues and principles pertinent to their practitioners as well. See Pellegrino (2001).

  13. In a synthesis of the literature (Molina et al. 2014) about resilience in different stages of cancer, with a patient-centered care focus, the review provided important information to consider at each stage of the continuum and offered healthcare providers and researcher different forms of resilience to incorporate in the patient care process. The authors concluded that promoting resilience is a critical element of patient-centered psychosocial care, and multidisciplinary healthcare teams can foster resilience by recognizing and improving features of resilience through the cancer continuum. A strong commitment from healthcare teams is needed in order to develop programs and interventions oriented to foster resilience in patients.

  14. Some of these skills are: (a) sensitivity to consider the context of the person and his or her illness from his or her own perspective, (b) highlight the importance of the individual context, and not only in the context of a systematic description of the disease and its etiology, (c) narrative communication skills: exploring differences and connections, hypothesizing, strategizing, sharing power, reflection active listening, and circular questioning and (d) self-reflection.

  15. According to Iris Marion Young (1990), there are “five faces of oppression”: violence, exploitation, marginalization, powerlessness, and cultural imperialism. In these five categories, she conveys how the social constructs affect and shape the individual. Each of these forms of oppression overlaps with the other. This framework focuses on the ways in which people experience oppressive conditions in their daily lives.

  16. Thesen explains in her article that she started thinking about the problem of oppression after conducting a study of the experience of users of psychiatric services (in this article called "Study of experience"). Users described dehumanizing experiences of being reclassified as the stigmatized "other". She explains that they presented convincing and harsh experiences of oppression, lack of love and lack of life of their own, mainly in their encounter with people from their local community, but also in health and social services. Her findings led her to think that the dominant person in a human encounter sometimes stigmatizes and harasses the other, and that doctors are no exception. After this research, she asked herself why doctors like herself assume the role of oppressor in medical encounters. She also asked herself if the reason for that is due to personal deficiencies, or if there is a more structural reason. She decided to try to explain how the oppressive process could be described. Another concern she expresses arose from this previous study is that if she recognizes that sometimes she acted as an oppressor of her patients, how could this behavior change? And finally, why this type of behavior is invisible for the clinicians.

  17. The article published by Carel is written as a response to Sellman ́s article, confronting some of their arguments. That is why she uses the same terminology that Sellman. Sellman distinguish between ordinarily vulnerable people and more-than-ordinarily vulnerable people. While all people are vulnerable, all patients are more-than-ordinarily vulnerable and this restricts their potential to flourish. For him, nurses are well placed to contribute to the flourishing of more-than-ordinarily vulnerable persons and he claims that this ‘protective’ function is a legitimate and fundamental part of the role of nurses.

  18. Kimberly Manning is a hospitalist at Grady Memorial Hospital in Atlanta, an associate professor of medicine at Emory, and an adviser in the Semmelweiss Society. Her interests include humanism in medicine and the use of reflective writing. She practices what she preaches by writing a blog about her experiences at Grady. “I write to share the human aspects of medicine and teaching and work-life balance,” Manning says, “and to honor the public hospital and her patients, but never at the expense of patient privacy or dignity.” She also writes about her frustrations and ways that she stays energized and optimistic in the face of daunting amounts of human tragedy. Usually, she copes very well, finding joy in the job on most days. This is not a story about one of those days. To read the whole story, visit http://www.gradydoctor.com/2017/07/heavy-on-my-soul.html. (last visited July 8, 2020).

  19. The authors highlight that all professions in healthcare experience similar effects in relation to the stressful conditions of work. This common aspect offers an opportunity to design and implement inter-professional approaches that can enhance the capacity for resilience among teams of coworkers.

  20. Moral distress was originally described by Andrew Jameton (1984), and occurs when a healthcare professional makes a moral judgment about a case in which he or she is involved and an external constraint makes it difficult or impossible to act on that judgment, and he or she experiences painful feelings and/or psychological disequilibrium. He developed the term in the context of the explanation of the manners through institutional policies and practices can lead professionals to act in a way that they consider morally wrong. In this relation between organization and staff, moral distress can arise when the workers cannot perform their duties in a manner according to their moral values. In many cases, the reasons may be directly related to the institution.

  21. The relationship between burnout and clinical error is understood as bidirectional. Dyrbye et al. (2017) shown several studies in which self-perceived medical errors were associated with worsening burn out, depressive symptoms, and decreased quality of life, suggesting a cyclical relationship between medical errors and distress. In addition, they shown other studies that have found that as the average levels of burn out of physicians and nurses working in intensive care units increased, so did the standardized rates of patient mortality, while the perceived quality of work in interpersonal equipment deteriorated (Dyrbye et al. 2017). They conclude that burn out among healthcare professionals is related to quality and safety, patient satisfaction and healthcare costs.

  22. Nancy Berlinger (2016, p. 176) has analyzed these disruptions between ideals and reality broadly: “There are limits to thinking of professional ethics in terms of virtues- being caring, being compassionate, being respectful- if healthcare professionals see few ways to put these virtues into practice. Framing professional ethics in terms of an idealized physician -patient relationship is insufficient, as this is closed off from the reality of the complex system professionals and patients have to contend with. Similarly, describing the duties of health care professionals is insufficient without acknowledging the conditions of complexity and how flawed systems can impede individual or team efforts to do good and prevent harm (…) Thinking about the complex systems as a "moral space" that must always be open to the discussion of questions of right and wrong action, of justice and injustice, may help us grapple with the continuing challenge of creating and sustaining health care systems that are safe, effective, compassionate and just”.

  23. Triple aim refers a series of goals that the United States must follow to achieve high-value healthcare. Those goals are called the “Triple Aim”: improving the individual experience of care; improving the health of populations; and reducing the per capita costs of care for populations. See Berwick et al. 2008.

References

  • Abed-Ali, Diaa, Hassan A. Athbi, and Safi D. Nawam. 2016. Impact of nurses’ burnout on patients’ satisfaction with nursing care in Al-Najaf City. International Journal of Scientific and Research Publications 6 (1): 186–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, Wendy. 2006. Engagement in contemporary practice: A relational ethics perspective. Texto Contexto Enfermagem 15: 135–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, Anne. 1994. Moral Prejudices: Essays on ethics. New York: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard, David. 2016. Vulnerability and trustworthiness: Polestars of professionalism in healthcare. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (2): 288–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beach, Mary Catherine, and Thomas Inui. 2006. Relationship-centered care. Journal of General Internal Medicine 21 (S1): S3–S8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlinger, Nancy. 2016. Are workaround ethical? Managing moral problems in health care systems. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, Donald M., Thomas W. Nolan, and John Whittington. 2008. The triple aim: Care, health, and cost. Health Affairs 27 (3): 759–769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigham, Timothy, Connie Barden, Anne L. Dopp, Art Hengerer, et al. 2018. A Journey to Construct an All-Encompassing Conceptual Model of Factors Affecting Clinician Well-Being and Resilience. Perspectives. National Academy of Medicine.

  • Butler, Judith. 2006. Precarious life The power of the mourning and violence. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2009. Frames of war. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel, Havi. 2009. A reply to ‘towards an understanding of nursing as a response to human vulnerability’ by Derek Sellman: Vulnerability and illness. Nursing Philosophy 10: 214–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrese, Joseph A., Janet Malek, Katie Watson, et al. 2015. The essential role of medical ethics education in achieving professionalism: The Romanell Report. Academic Medicine 90 (6): 744–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delgado, Janet. 2017. The relevance of the ethics of vulnerability in bioethics. Les ateliers de l’éthique 12 (2–3): 154–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, Susan. 2001. Trust and the ethics of health care institutions. Hastings Center Report 31 (6): 26–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doukas, David J., Laurence B. McCullough, Stephen Wear, Project to Rebalance and Integrate Medical Education (PRIME) Investigators, et al. 2013. The challenge of promoting professionalism through medical ethics and humanities education. Academic Medicine 88 (11): 1624–1629.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyrbye, Lotte N, Tait Shanafelt, Christine A. Sinsky, Pamela Cipriano, et al. 2017. Burnout among health care professionals a call to explore and address this under recognized threat to safe, High-Quality. NAM Perspectives, Discussion Paper.

  • Dzau, Victor J., Darrell G. Kirch, and Thomas J. Nasca. 2018. To care is human—collectively confronting the clinician-burnout crisis. New England Journal of Medicine 378 (4): 312–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feito, Lydia. 2007. Vulnerabilidad/vulnerability. Anales Sistema Sanitario Navarra. 30 (3): 7–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2008. The vulnerable subject: Anchoring equality in the human condition. Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 20: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2010. The vulnerable subject and the responsive state. Emory Law Journal 60: 251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2012. “Elderly” as vulnerable: Rethinking the nature of individual and societal responsibility. The Elder Law Journal. 20 (1): 71–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2014. Vulnerability, resilience, and LGBT youth. Temple Political & Civil Rights Law Review, Forthcoming; Emory legal studies research paper 14: 292.

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2015. Equality and difference: the restrained state. Alabama Law Review 66 (3): 609–626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, Martha A. 2017. Vulnerability and inevitable inequality. Oslo Law Review 4: 133–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilson, Erinn C. 2014. The ethics of vulnerability: A feminist analysis of social life and practice. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gjengedal, Eva, Else Mary Ekra, Hege Hol, Marianne Kjelsvik, et al. 2013. Vulnerability in health care—reflections on encounters in every day practice. Nursing Philosophy 14: 127–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbesleben, Jonathon R.H.., Bonnie J. Wakefield, Douglas S. Wakefield, and Lynn B. Cooper. 2008. Nurse burnout and patient safety outcomes: Nurse safety perception versus reporting behavior. Western Journal of Nursing research 30 (5): 560–577.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, Louise H., Judith Johnson, Ian Watt, Anastasia Tsipa, and Daryl B. O’Connor. 2016. Healthcare staff wellbeing, burnout, and patient safety: A systematic review. PLoS ONE 11 (7): e0159015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haramati, Aviad, and Peggy A. Weissinger. 2015. Resilience, empathy, and wellbeing in the health professions: An educational imperative. Global Advances in Health and Medicine 4 (5): 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, Virginia. 2006. The ethics of care: Personal, political, and global. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurst, Samia A. 2008. Vulnerability in research and health care; describing the elephant in the room? Bioethics 22 (4): 191–202. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2008.00631.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameton, Andrew. 1984. Nursing practice: The ethical issues. Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalitzkus, Vera, and Peter F. Matthiessen. 2009. Narrative-based medicine: Potential, pitfalls, and practice. The Permanante Journal 13 (1): 80–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp, Peter and Jakob Rendtorff, Jakob. 2008.The Barcelona Declaration. Synthesis philosophica 46: 239–251.

  • Kerasidou, Angeliki, and Ruth Horn. 2016. Making space for empathy: Supporting doctors in the emotional labour of clinical care. BMC Medical Ethics 17: 8. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-016-0091-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirwan, Marcia, Anne Matthews, and P. Anne Scott. 2013. The impact of the work environment of nurses on patient safety outcomes: A multi-level modelling approach. International Journal of Nursing Studies 50 (2): 253–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kittay, Eva. 1999. Love’s labor: Essays on women, equality, and dependency. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1961. Totalité et Infini: Essai sur l'extériorité. Translation Levinas, E. Totalidad e infinito. Salamanca: Sígueme, 1977.

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1972. Humanisme del'autre homme. Translation Levinas, E. Humanismo del otro hombre. Madrid: Ed Caparrós, 1998.

  • Levine, Carol, Ruth Faden, Christine Grady, Dale Hammerschmidt, Lisa Eckenwiler, and Jeremy Sugarman. 2004. The limitations of ‘vulnerability’ as a protection for human research participants. The American Journal of Bioethics 4 (3): 44–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luna, Florencia. 2006. Bioethics and vulnerability: A Latin American view. Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luna, Florencia. 2008. Vulnerabilidad: La metáfora de las capas. Jurisprudencia Argentina, IV 1: 60–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luna, Florencia. 2009. Elucidating the concept of vulnerability. Layers not labels. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 1: 120–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malterud, Kristi, and Hanne Hollnagel. 2005. The doctor who cried: A qualitative study about the doctor’s vulnerability. Annals of Family Medicine 3 (4): 348–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malterud, Kristi, and Per Solvang. 2005. Vulnerability as a strength: Why, when, and how? Scandinavian Journal of Public Health 33 (66): 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malterud, Kristi, Lisse Fredriksen, and Mete Haukaas Gjerde. 2009. When doctors experience their vulnerability as beneficial for the patients. A focus-group study from general practice. Scandinavian Journal of Primary Health Care 27: 85–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, Wendy Rogers, and Susan Dodds. 2014. Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy (studies in feminist philosophy). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 2006. Dependent rational animals. Why human beings need the virtues. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Angela, and Samia Hurst. 2017. On vulnerability—analysis and applications of a many-faceted concept: Introduction. In Les ateliers de l’éthique/the ethics forum. Montréal: Centre de recherche en éthique de l’Université de Montréal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medical Professionalism Project. 2002. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physicians’ charter. The Lancet 359 (9305): 520–522.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milliken, Aimee, and Pamela Grace. 2015. Nurse ethical awareness: Understanding the nature of everyday practice. Nursing Ethics 24: 517–524.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molina, Yamile, Jean C. Yi, Javiera Martinez-Gutierrez, Kerryn W. Reding, Joyce P. Yi-Frazier, and Abby R. Rosenberg. 2014. Resilience among patients across the cancer continuum: Diverse perspectives. Clinical Journal of Oncology Nursing 18 (1): 93–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, Cristina. 2016. Conflictos éticos y acciones de resistencia: Los profesionales de atención primaria de Mallorca frente a los recortes en el sistema público de salud. Palma: Universitat de les Illes Balears.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, Nel. 1984. Caring, a feminine approach to ethics & moral education. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nundy, Shantanu, and John Oswald. 2014. Relationship-centered care: A new paradigm for population health management. Healthcare 2: 216–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neves, Patrão, and C. Maria do. 2009. Respect for human vulnerability and personal integrity. In The UNESCO universal declaration on bioethics and human rights background, principles and application, ed. Ten Have Henk and Jean Michele. Paris: UNESCO Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, David. 2018. Moral distress in hospital doctors. BMJ, 36

  • Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2001. The internal morality of clinical medicine: A paradigm for the ethics of the helping and healing professions. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26 (6): 559–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2012. Medical ethics in an era of bioethics: Resetting the medical profession ́s compass. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33 (1): 21–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perni, Subha. 2017. Moral distress: A call to action. AMA Journal of Ethics 19 (6): 533–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peroni, Lourdes, and Alexandra Timmer. 2013. ‘Vulnerable groups: The promise of an emerging concept in european human rights convention law. International Journal of Constitutional Law 11 (4): 1056–1085.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Robert L., Andrew W. Bazemore, Warren P. Newton, Richard L. Byyny. 2019. Medical professionalism: A contract with society. The Pharos 2–7.

  • Pipe, Teresa Britt, Vicki L. Buchda, Susan Launder, Barb Hudak, Lynne Hulvey, Katherine E. Karns, and Debra Pendergast. 2012. Building personal and professional resources of resilience and agility in the healthcare workplace. Stress and Health 28: 11–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rendtorff, Jacob D. and Peter Kemp. 2000. Basic ethical principles in European bioethics and biolaw: Partners' research. Centre for Ethics and Law.

  • Rendtorff, Jacob D. 2002. Basic ethical principles in European bioethics and biolaw: Autonomy, dignity, integrity and vulnerability. towards a foundation of bioethics and biolaw. Medicine Health Care and Philosophy 5: 235–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, Joel M. 2016. Infinite responsibility in the Bedpan: Response ethics, care ethics, and the phenomenology of dependency work. Hypatia 31 (4): 779–794.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricouer, Paul. 2000. Reflections on the just. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, Ivan T., Cary L. Cooper, Mustafa Sarkar, and Thomas Curran. 2015. Resilience training in the workplace from 2003 to 2014: A systematic review. Journal of Occupational and Organizational Psychology 88 (3): 533–562.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, Wendy, Catriona Mackenzie, and Susan Dodds. 2012. Why bioethics needs a concept of vulnerability. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 5 (2): 11–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Jacqueline. 2016. The connection between burnout and patient safety. Journal of PeriAnesthesia Nursing 31 (6): 539–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellman, Derek. 2005. Towards an understanding of nursing as a response to human vulnerability. Nursing Philosophy 6: 2–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Johanna, Lois L. Nixon, Stephen E. Wear, and David J. Doukas. 2015. Medical professionalism: What the study of literature can contribute to the conversation. Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine 10: 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straehle, Christine. 2017. Vulnerability, autonomy and applied ethics. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Squiers, John, Kevin W. Lobdell, James I. Fann, and J. Michael DMaio, J. M. 2017. Physician Burnout: Are We Treating the Symptoms Instead of the Disease? Annals of Thoracic Surgery; 104:1117–1122.

  • ten Have, Henk. 2016. Vulnerability: Challenging Bioethics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thesen, Janecke. 2005. From oppression towards empowerment in clinical practice: Offering doctors a model for reflection. Scand Journal of Public Health 66: 47–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral boundaries: A political argument for an ethic of care. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Bryan. 2006. Vulnerability and human rights. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, Connie M., and Christine Grady. 2018. Moral distress in the health professions. New York: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, Connie M., Carol Taylor, Karen Soeken, Patricia O’Donnell, Adrienne Farrar, Marion Danis, and Christine Grady. 2010. Everyday ethics: Ethical issues and stress in nursing practice. Journal of Advanced Nurse 66 (11): 2510–2519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vahey, Doris C., Linda H. Aiken, Douglas M. Sloane, Sean P. Clarke, and Delfino Vargas. 2004. Nurse burnout and patient satisfaction. Medical Care 42 (2): 1157–1166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vivanco, Luis, and R. Roberto Delgado-Bolton. 2015. Professionalism. In Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics, ed. H. ten Have, 2312–2319. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagorac, Ivana. 2017. What vulnerability? Whose vulnerability? Conflict of understandings in the debate on vulnerability. Facta Universitatis Series: Law and Politics 15 (2): 157–169.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Janet Delgado.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Delgado, J. Vulnerability as a key concept in relational patient- centered professionalism. Med Health Care and Philos 24, 155–172 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-020-09995-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-020-09995-8

Keywords

Navigation