Skip to main content
Log in

Randomization and dynamic consistency

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Raiffa (Q J Econ 75:690–694, 1961) has suggested that ambiguity aversion will cause a strict preference for randomization. We show that dynamic consistency implies that individuals will be indifferent to ex ante randomizations. On the other hand, it is possible for a dynamically consistent ambiguity averse preference relation to exhibit a strict preference for some ex post randomizations. We argue that our analysis throws some light on the recent debate on the status of the smooth model of ambiguity This debate rests on whether the randomizations implicit in the set-up are viewed as being resolved before or after the (ambiguous) uncertainty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Numerous experiments have confirmed this observation; Camerer and Weber (1992), Trautmann and van de Kuilen (2015).

  2. Raiffa (1961) considers the original composition of the Ellsberg urn with 30 red balls and 60 balls which were either black or yellow. Unlike the standard 3-colour Ellsberg urn, in the modified example, slightly less than one-third of the balls are red.

  3. See also the discussion in Ghirardato (1997).

  4. See in particular Wakker (2010) Sections 4.9 and 10.7.

  5. Anscombe and Aumann (1963, p. 201), Assumption 2 (Reversal of order of compound lotteries).

  6. The ex post randomizations in this framework may be identified with a subset of the horserace-lottery acts in the AA framework. In particular, the ex post randomization \(f_{D}g\) may be identified with the horserace-lottery act H where for each s in S, \(H\left( s\right) =\mu \left( D\right) \delta _{f(S)}+\left( 1-\mu \left( D\right) \right) \delta _{g(S)}\) and \(\delta _{x}\) is the degenerate lottery that yields the outcome x with probability 1. That is, an ex post randomization can be naturally identified with a horserace-lottery act in which the second stage is a binary lottery.

  7. This can be seen as a weak version of the AA reversal of order assumption, which only applies to acts which are independent of the S-states.

  8. This assumption is similar in spirit to the device independence assumption in Eichberger and Kelsey (1996).

  9. If \(a\in A\left( {\varOmega }\right) \) then for given rs, \(a\left( r,s,\cdot \right) \) is an act whose outcome only depends on the ex post randomizing device and hence may be described by a distribution function \(F_{a\left( r,s,\cdot \right) }\).

  10. Since we use a specific filtration our axioms are not symmetric between the ex post and ex ante randomizations.

  11. In this sense it may also be viewed as a weaker form of the “coherence” condition of Skiadas (1997), expression (6) p. 353.

  12. This may be viewed as a special case of ‘issue preference’, as in Ergin and Gul (2009), or ‘source dependence’, as in Chew and Sagi (2008).

  13. This can be made compatible with our assumption that the R-space is a continuum by identifying \(r_{1}\) with \(\left[ 0,\frac{1}{2}\right] \subseteq R\), and \(r_{2}\) with \(\left( \frac{1}{2},1\right] \subseteq R\).

  14. One may find this result less compelling in a normative sense than a strict preference which violates dynamic consistency. If preferences satisfy an appropriate continuity property, however, then we can construct a violation of dynamic consistency which only involves strict preferences. The argument in the introduction provides an outline of the proof.

  15. Bade (2011) makes a related point. She shows that, in a strategic setting, an ambiguous randomizing device would not help a player in a game. In her model the equilibria with ambiguous randomizations coincide with conventional Nash equilibria.

  16. The indifference \(\left( x_{C}y\right) E\left( y_{C}x\right) \thicksim \left( x_{C}y\right) E\left( x_{C}y\right) \) arises because \(\mu \left( C\right) =1/2\) implies that \(\left( x_{C}y\right) \) and \(\left( y_{C}x\right) \) give the same outcomes with the same probabilities. Intuitively they should be indifferent conditional on \(E^{c}\). Indifference is implied by Assumption 2.1 which says objective randomizations with the same probabilities are indifferent and if they have the same conditional probabilities they are indifferent in the corresponding conditional preferences.

  17. In the quotation, the notation of events and acts has been adapted to the one used in this paper.

  18. As in the previous quotation, we have adapted the notation to the one used in this paper.

  19. There is also an earlier literature, see for instance, Brewer (1963) or Fellner (1963).

References

  • Anscombe, F.J., Aumann, R.J.: A definition of subjective probability. Ann. Math. Stat. 34, 199–205 (1963)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bade, S.: Ambiguous act equilibria. Games Econ. Behav. 71, 246–260 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bade, S.: Randomization devices and the elicitation of ambiguity-averse preferences. J. Econ. Theory 159, 221–235 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, K.: Decisions under uncertainty: comment. Q. J. Econ. 77, 159–161 (1963)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C.F., Weber, M.W.: Recent developments in modelling preferences: uncertainty and ambiguity. J. Risk Uncertain. 5, 325–370 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S.H., Sagi, J.: Small worlds: modeling attitudes towards sources of uncertainty. J. Econ. Theory 139, 1–24 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dominiak, A., Schnedler, W.: Attitudes towards uncertainty and randomization: an experimental study. Econ. Theory 48, 289–312 (2011). doi:10.1007/s00199-011-0649-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Kelsey, D.: Uncertainty aversion and preference for randomization. J. Econ. Theory 71, 31–43 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Grant, S., Kelsey, D.: CEU preferences and dynamic consistency. Math. Soc. Sci. 49, 143–151 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Oechssler, J., Schnedler, W.: How do subjects view multiple sources of ambiguity? Theory Decis. 78, 339–356 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D.: Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 75, 643–669 (1961)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G.: A paradox for the ‘smooth ambiguity’ model of preference. Econometrica 78, 2085–2099 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G., Schneider, M.: Recursive multiple-priors. J. Econ. Theory 113, 1–31 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ergin, H., Gul, F.: A theory of subjective compound lotteries. J. Econ. Theory 144, 899–929 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fellner, W.: Slanted subjective probabilities and randomization. Q. J. Econ. 77, 676–690 (1963)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P.: On independence for non-additive measures and a Fubini theorem. J. Econ. Theory 73, 261–291 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D.: Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. J. Math. Econ. 18, 141–153 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karni, E., Safra, Z.: Preference reversal and the observability of preferences by experimental methods. Econometrica 55, 675–685 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.M.: The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money. Macmillan, London (1936)

    Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff, P.: Stochastically independent randomization and uncertainty aversion. Econ. Theory 18, 605–620 (2001). doi:10.1007/PL00004201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., Mukerji, S.: A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73(6), 1849–1892 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., Mukerji, S.: On the smooth ambiguity model: a reply. Econometrica 80(3), 1303–1321 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F.H.: Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Houghton Mifflin, New York (1921)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.: The Theory of Choice Under Uncertainty. Westview, New York (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuzmics, C.: Abraham Wald’s complete class theorem and Knightian uncertainty. Working paper, Bielefeld University (2015)

  • Machina, M.: Dynamic consistency and non-expected utility models of choice under uncertainty. J. Econ. Lit. 27, 1622–1668 (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M., Schmeidler, D.: A more robust definition of subjective probability. Econometrica 60, 745–780 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa, H.: Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms: comment. Q. J. Econ. 75, 690–694 (1961)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saito, K.: Subjective timing of randomisation and ambiguity. Working paper, California Institute of Technology (2013)

  • Sarin, R., Wakker, P.: Dynamic choice and non-expected utility. J. Risk and Uncertain. 17, 87–120 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.J.: Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York (1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D.: Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica 57, 571–587 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seo, K.: Ambiguity and second order belief. Econometrica 77, 1575–1605 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skiadas, C.: Conditioning and aggregation of preferences. Econometrica 65, 347–367 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann, S.T., van de Kuilen, G.: Ambiguity attitudes. In: Keren, G., Wu, G. (eds.) The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, vol. 1, pp. 89–116. Wiley-Blackwell, New York (2015)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.: Prospect Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2010)

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Kelsey.

Additional information

Research supported by a Leverhulme Research Fellowship. We would like to thank the referee and editor of this journal, Peter Klibanoff, Tigran Melkonyan, Zvi Safra, Marciano Siniscalchi, Peter Wakker and seminar audiences at the Universities of Bristol, Cergy-Pontoise, Exeter, LSE and RUD 2013 for helpful comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eichberger, J., Grant, S. & Kelsey, D. Randomization and dynamic consistency. Econ Theory 62, 547–566 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0913-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0913-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation