Skip to main content
Log in

Allometries and scaling laws interpreted as laws: a reply to Elgin

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I analyze here biological regression equations known in the literature as allometries and scaling laws. My focus is on the alleged lawlike status of these equations. In particular I argue against recent views that regard allometries and scaling laws as representing universal, non-continent, and/or strict biological laws. Although allometries and scaling laws appear to be generalizations applying to many taxa, they are neither universal nor exceptionless. In fact there appear to be exceptions to all of them. Nor are the constants in allometries and scaling laws truly constant, stable, or universal in character, but vary in value across different taxa and background conditions. Moreover, these equations represent evolutionary, strongly contingent generalizations, which threatens their lawlike status. Lastly, allometries and scaling laws do not offer stable probabilities to which they hold in different backgrounds. I further suggest that many allometries and scaling laws function to elucidate explananda rather than explanantia or covering laws.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lawlikeness is not only the distinctive property of laws; it is also the property that gives laws their support in counterfactuals or subjunctives. Counterfactual support of laws tells how laws govern not just what actually happens, but what would have happened under certain background conditions had they happened. In other words, laws do not just describe what happens in the world, but they also dictate what must happen and what would happen had the conditions been such-and-such or this-and-that. That laws support counterfactuals is what gives laws explanatory and predictive power, modal force, and necessity—or least it illuminates how they get these qualities. Given the points just outlined, it is natural to suppose that laws would be something over and above things that elucidate data from phenomena, namely, that they function as explanantia of phenomena.

  2. According to Bergmann’s rule, the members of a species of (endothermic) animals are larger in their body size in colder regions or at higher latitudes than members of the same species in warmer regions or at lower latitudes. According to Cope’s rule, there is a general evolutionary trend toward larger body size in many taxa.

  3. There is a distinction between allometries and scaling laws in the literature that is irrelevant to the present discussion: “‘[A]llometry’ is used to denote changes internal to the organisms that occur with size change (e.g., anatomical, metabolism, physiology). For changes external to the individual, such as in population density, predator or prey size, that occur with body-size increase, I use… [the] term’scaling’… This should help distinguish between two qualitatively different kinds of change that occur as an organism increases in size, dichotomising the changes that occur within the individual and those that reflect changes in interactions with its abiotic and biotic external environment” (McKinney 1990: 78).

  4. I have omitted error terms that represent variation in the dependent variable due to other possible independent variables and measurement errors in the independent variable.

  5. The evolutionary contingency thesis, along with many responses to it and its implications, for the existence of biological laws are discussed and analyzed in more detail by me elsewhere (see Raerinne forthcoming: Chapters 2 and 5). Although many think of weak contingency or “exceptions” as the central problem in the context of biological generalizations’ lawlikeness, this is probably a misapprehension, since there are accounts of laws that tolerate exceptions to them, such as the ceteris paribus account and the account that views biological generalizations as probabilistic laws. In other words, the central problem for the lawlikeness of biological generalizations is their strong contingency rather than weak contingency.

  6. The Hardy–Weinberg rule describes what will happen to gene and genotype frequencies in a population unaffected by evolutionary forces according to which both gene frequencies and genotype frequencies will remain constant in successive generations.

  7. Its probabilistic formulation would not affect the point I made here.

  8. I have discussed and criticized the ceteris paribus account of laws elsewhere (see Raerinne 2003), where I argue that the account raises several empirical, epistemological, and semantic problems that are unresolved, at least given the proposal of ceteris paribus laws in the literature (see also Schiffer 1991; Mott 1992; Wallis 1994; Earman and Roberts 1999; Schurz 2001, 2002; Earman et al. 2002; Mitchell 2002; Woodward 2002). In other words, it has proven to be difficult to define exactly what ceteris paribus clauses mean. If a more precise meaning or semantics is not given, then we have generalizations that are empirically, epistemologically, and semantically vague.

  9. Mitchell (1997, 2000), Lange (1993, 2005), and many others have suggested redefining laws—at least in part to respond to Beatty’s evolutionary contingency thesis—to redeem the lawlike status of biological generalizations. I have criticized such re-definitions of laws elsewhere (see Raerinne forthcoming: Chapters 3 and 5).

  10. In developing the above argument, I had ecological and paleobiological generalizations in mind. Some authors have suggested that generalizations from evolutionary biology, such as what Brandon (2006) have dubbed as “the principle of drift,” could be probabilistic laws. Although I think that the argument just presented applies to biological generalizations in general, I shall not argue for this here.

  11. According to the latitudinal diversity gradient, there exist a geographical or latitudinal gradient in species richness or diversity according to which the number of species within a taxonomic group tends to increase with decreasing latitudes, i.e., diversity increases towards the tropics and decreases towards the poles.

References

  • Ashton KG, Tracy MC, de Queiroz A (2000) Is Bergmann’s rule valid for mammals? Am. Nat. 156:390–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Wolters G, Lennox JG (eds) Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences. Universitätsverlag Konstanz, Konstanz, pp 45–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J, Woodward J (1988) Saving the phenomena. Philos. Rev. 97:303–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (2006) The principle of drift: biology’s first law. J. Philos. 101:319–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown JH (1995) Macroecology. Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Clutton-Brock TH, Harvey PH (1983) The functional significance of variation in body size among mammals. In: Eisenberg JF, Kleiman DG (eds) Advances in the study of mammalian behavior. American Society of Mammalogists, Shippensburg (Pennsylvania), pp 632–663

    Google Scholar 

  • Dale FH (1940) Geographic variation in the meadow mouse in British Columbia and Southeastern Alaska. J. Mammalogy 21:332–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damuth J (1981) Population density and body size in mammals. Nature 290:699–700

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damuth J (1991) Of size and abundance. Nature 351:268–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis WB (1938) Relation of size of pocket gophers to soil and altitude. J Mammalogy 19:338–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J, Roberts J (1999) Ceteris Paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese 118:439–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J, Roberts J, Smith S (2002) Ceteris Paribus lost. Erkenntnis 57:281–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin M (2006) There may be strict empirical laws in biology, after all. Biol Philos 21:119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freckleton RP, Harvey PH, Pagel M (2003) Bergmann’s rule and body size in mammals. Am. Nat. 161:821–825

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaston KJ (1996) Biodiversity: latitudinal gradients. Progr. Phys. Geogr. 20:466–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geist V (1987) Bergmann’s rule is invalid. Can J Zool 65:1035–1038

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1966) Allometry and size in ontogeny and phylogeny. Biol Rev 41:587–640

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagmeier EM, Stults C (1964) A numerical analysis of the distributional patterns of North American mammals. Syst Zool 13:125–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (1993) Lawlikeness. Noûs 27:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange M (2005) Laws and their stability. Synthese 144:415–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquet PA (2000) Invariants, scaling laws, and ecological complexity. Science 289:1487–1488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquet PA, Quiñones RA, Abades S, Labra F, Tognelli M, Arim M, Rivadeneira M (2005) Scaling and power-laws in ecological systems. J Exp Biol 208:1749–1769

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinney ML (1990) Trends in body-size evolution. In: McNamara KJ (ed) Evolutionary trends. Univ. of Arizona Press, Tucson, pp 75–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (1997) Pragmatic laws. Philos. Sci. 64:S468–S479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (2000) Dimensions of scientific law. Philos. Sci. 67:242–265

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (2002) Ceteris Paribus—an inadequate representation for biological contingency. Erkenntnis 57:329–350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mott P (1992) Fodor and Ceteris Paribus laws. Mind 101:335–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell ND (1949) Phyletic size increase, an important trend illustrated by fossil invertebrates. Evolution 3:103–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters RH (1983) The ecological implications of body size. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabenold KN (1979) A reversed latitudinal diversity gradient in avian communities of eastern deciduous forests. Am. Nat. 114:275–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raerinne JP (2003) Erityistieteiden Ceteris Paribus-lait: Pohdintoja semantiikan ja sisällön ongelmista ja postuloinnin tarpeesta. Master’s Thesis, Department of Social and Moral Philosophy, Univ. of Helsinki, Finland. Available at URL http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/julkaisut/val/kayta/pg/raerinne/

  • Raerinne JP (forthcoming) Generalizations and models in ecology: lawlikeness, invariance, stability, and robustness. Doctoral Dissertation, Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies, Univ. of Helsinki, Finland

  • Ralls K, Harvey PH (1985) Geographic variation in size and sexual dimorphism of North American weasels. Biol J Linn Soc 25:119–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rensch B (1960) The laws of evolution. In: Tax S (ed) Evolution after darwin: the evolution of life, vol 1. Univ. of Chicago, Chicago, pp 95–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1973) The philosophy of biology. London, Hutchinson

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S (1991) Ceteris Paribus laws. Mind 100:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz G (2001) Pietroski and rey on Ceteris Paribus laws. Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 52:359–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz G (2002) Ceteris Paribus laws: classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis 57:351–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1997) Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of science. Philos. Sci. 64:S458–S467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallis C (1994) Ceteris Paribus laws and psychological explanations. In: Hull D, Forbes M, Burian RM (eds) PSA 1994, vol 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 388–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (1989) Data and phenomena. Synthese 79:393–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2000) Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 51:197–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2002) There is no such thing as a Ceteris Paribus law. Erkenntnis 57:303–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The work was supported financially by the Academy of Finland as a part of the project Modelling Mechanisms: A New Approach to Scientific Understanding and Inter-Disciplinary Integration (project number 112 2818). I am grateful to Markus Eronen and two anonymous referees for this journal that provided helpful comments and suggestions on a previous draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jani Raerinne.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Raerinne, J. Allometries and scaling laws interpreted as laws: a reply to Elgin. Biol Philos 26, 99–111 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9203-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9203-9

Keywords

Navigation