Skip to main content
Log in

Dynamic homology and circularity in cladistic analysis

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, I examine the issue of the alleged circularity in the determination of homologies within cladistic analysis. More specifically, I focus on the claims made by the proponents of the dynamic homology approach, regarding the distinction (sometimes made in the literature) between primary and secondary homology. This distinction is sometimes invoked to dissolve the circularity issue, by upholding that characters in a cladistic data matrix have to be only primarily homologous, and thus can be determined independently of phylogenetic hypotheses, by using the classical Owenian criteria (for morphological characters) or via multiple sequence alignment (for sequence data). However, since in the dynamic approach, sequence data can be analyzed without being pre-aligned, proponents have claimed that the distinction between primary and secondary homology has no place within cladistics. I will argue that this is not the case, since cladistic practice within the dynamic framework does presuppose primary homology statements at a higher level.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this article, I focus on cladistic (i.e. maximum parsimony) approaches to phylogenetic reconstruction, leaving out other currently used methods such as maximum likelihood and Bayesian analysis. However, much of what I will say here will be applicable to those methods as well, since the dynamic homology approach has been applied to them as well (e.g. Wheeler 2006 for likelihood, Herman et al. 2014 for Bayesian inference). With the term ‘cladistics’ I am referring solely to the method of phylogenetic reconstruction, not to any views about classification (see Quinn 2017 for the various uses of the term).

  2. A similar point has been raised regarding the concept of adaptation, see e.g. Ginnobili (2018, pp. 26–31) and references therein.

  3. This corresponds to what Martin et al. (2010) call a node-based reading of phylogenetic trees; those authors show that there are other, equivalent, ways of interpreting trees. There has also been some discussion over whether cladograms and phylogenetic trees are equivalent, and what each represents (see e.g. Platnick 1977; Wiley 1979). I shall not go into these nuances, since they will not affect my points.

  4. If more than one tree has the same minimum length, then cladists will not typically choose one among them arbitrarily. Instead, they will present some consensus tree between all the optimal trees. For instance, the strict consensus tree will only contain the groups that are present in all the optimal trees (see Kitching et al. 1998, chapter 7).

  5. Again, there are many possible complications here, which do not always allow one to get a single optimal homology scheme. For instance, as mentioned above, cladistic analysis can yield more than one optimal tree, and those different trees can imply different homology schemes. Additionally, even a single tree can imply more than one possible scheme of homologies. For example, the tree in Fig. 2b can also be optimized by putting a 0 in all internal nodes, changing the homology scheme implied by it. I will not dig any deeper into these issues, since the general point made above will be enough for my purposes.

  6. This terminology is by de Pinna (1991), the article that has become an obligated reference on the subject. It can also be found (in some cases before de Pinna’s publication, as he himself acknowledges) as homology versus homogeny (Lankester 1870); hypotheses of homology versus homology (Patterson 1988); topographical correspondence versus homology (Rieppel 1988); etc. What I aim to show in this article is that dynamic analyses presuppose a data matrix that is built using the same (topological, compositional, etc.) criteria than those used in classical two-step analyses. Whether one calls the characters resulting from the application of these criteria homologies, primary homologies, hypotheses of homology or something that does not contain the term ‘homology’ at all (e.g. topographical correspondences) is irrelevant to my point. For simplicity’s sake, I will continue using de Pinna’s terminology.

  7. To clarify, in my view, secondary homologies are traits derived from a common ancestor, and cladistic analysis gives one way (but not the only way) of operationalizing this concept. Others might wish to directly define secondary homologies as the output of the method. Although interesting, this discussion has no impact on the conclusions drawn in this paper.

  8. In a static setting, characters can be revised after phylogenetic analysis has taken place, by recoding the data matrix that was used as its input and analyzing it again. This is a common characteristic of all science: one can revise the data after seeing how well they fare against the theoretical analysis of it (confirmation holism taught us this long ago). But what dynamic analyses do is different, they are effectively changing the theoretical analysis itself, and how it treats the data.

  9. The main (practical) disadvantage of the DO method is that it is computationally much more intensive than the traditional methodology.

  10. I am not claiming that individual sites are not characters, in the wider sense of characteristics that the study taxa possess, and that can therefore be compared and homologized (see above). I only state that, in a DO setting, the input matrix does not contain site-characters but rather loci-characters.

  11. The conceptual and mathematical apparatus used by Vogt is rather complex, and a fuller introduction and examination of it fall outside the scope of this article.

  12. All of this is not to deny that reciprocal illumination is a real phenomenon. As Hennig himself recognized (Hennig 1966, p. 21), it is not a phenomenon exclusive to phylogenetics. In all areas of science theories are tested through certain evidence, and at the same time the evidence can be modified to fit the theory. For example, if a theoretical prediction fails, one way to proceed is by revising the observations (either the initial conditions or the “observational” consequences), the measuring instruments, the auxiliary hypotheses, etc. In the philosophical literature this has long been known as confirmation holism. However, the occurrence of this phenomenon does not deny that the concepts in the explanandum of a theory have to be determinable independently of the theory for which they are explananda, on pain of circularity (as the structuralist school has long argued, and shown to be the case with multiple reconstructions of theories, see Balzer et al. 1987).

References

  • Agolin M, D’Haese CA (2009) An application of dynamic homology to morphological characters: direct optimization of setae sequences and phylogeny of the family Odontellidae (Poduromorpha, Collembola). Cladistics 25:353–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Balzer W, Moulines CU, Sneed JD (1987) An architectonic for science: the structuralist program. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanco D (2012) Primera aproximación estructuralista a la Teoría del Origen en Común. Ágora 31:171–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady R (1985) On the independence of systematics. Cladistics 1:113–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi G (2015) El impacto de la filosofía anatómica de Étienne Geoffoy Saint-Hilaire em el desarrollo de la historia natural. Gavagai - Rev Interdiscip Humanidades 2:9–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Ceccarelli FS, Koch NM, Soto EM, Barone ML, Arnedo MA, Ramirez MJ (2018) Data from: the grass was greener: repeated evolution of specialized morphologies and habitat shifts in ghost spiders following grassland expansion in South America, Dryad, Dataset. https://doi.org/10.5061/dryad.20257

  • Ceccarelli FS, Koch NM, Soto EM et al (2019) The grass was greener: repeated evolution of specialized morphologies and habitat shifts in ghost spiders following grassland expansion in South America. Syst Biol 68:63–77

    Google Scholar 

  • de Pinna MCC (1991) Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics 7:367–394

    Google Scholar 

  • Farris JS (2008) Parsimony and explanatory power. Cladistics 24:825–847

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2005) Evolution. Sinauer Associates Inc., Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili S (2018) Teoría de la Selección Natural. Una Exploración Metacientífica. Universidad Nacional de Quilmes, Bernal

    Google Scholar 

  • Giribet G, Wheeler WC (1999) On gaps. Mol Phylogenet Evol 13:132–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant T, Kluge A (2009) Perspective: parsimony, explanatory power, and dynamic homology testing. Syst Biodivers 7:357–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, Champaign

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman JL, Challis CJ, Novák Á et al (2014) Simultaneous Bayesian estimation of alignment and phylogeny under a joint model of protein sequence and structure. Mol Biol Evol 31:2251–2266

    Google Scholar 

  • Japyassú HF, Machado FdeA (2010) Coding behavioural data for cladistic analysis: using dynamic homology without parsimony. Cladistics 26:625–642

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine N (1967) The concept of homology in biology. Br J Philos Sci 18:125–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitching IJ, Forey PL, Humphries CJ, Williams DM (1998) Cladistics: the theory and practice of parsimony analysis, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG, Grant T (2006) From conviction to anti-superfluity: old and new justifications of parsimony in phylogenetic inference. Cladistics 22:276–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Lankester ER (1870) On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Ann Mag Nat Hist Zool Bot Geol 6:34–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin J, Blackburn D, Wiley EO (2010) Are node-based and stem-based clades equivalent? Insights from graph theory. PLOS Curr Tree Life. https://doi.org/10.1371/currents.RRN1196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Needleman SB, Wunsch CD (1970) A general method applicable to the search for similarities in the amino acid sequence of two proteins. J Mol Biol 48:443–453

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen R (1848) On the archetype and homologies of the vertebrate skeleton. John Van Voorst, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen R (1849) On the nature of limbs. John Van Voorst, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey KA, Friday AE (eds) Problems of phylogenetic reconstruction. Academic Press Inc., London, pp 21–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1988) Homology in classical and molecular biology. Mol Biol Evol 5:603–625

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson CH (2010) Pattern cladism, homology, and theory-neutrality. Hist Philos Life Sci 32:475–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Platnick NI (1977) Cladograms, phylogenetic trees, and hypothesis testing. Syst Biol 26:438–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn A (2017) When is a cladist not a cladist? Biol Philos 32:581–598

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramírez MJ (2007) Homology as a parsimony problem: a dynamic homology approach for morphological data. Cladistics 23:588–612

    Google Scholar 

  • Remane A (1952) Die Grundlagen des natürlichen Systems der vergleichenden Anatomie und der Phylogenetik. Geest & Portig, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1988) Fundamentals of comparative biology. Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2002) Similarity. Biol J Linn Soc 75:59–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2007) The poverty of taxonomic characters. Biol Philos 22:95–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Robillard T, Legendre F, Desutter-Grandcolas L, Grandcolas P (2006) Phylogenetic analysis and alignment of behavioral sequences by direct optimization. Cladistics 22:602–633

    Google Scholar 

  • Roffé AJ, Ginnobili S, Blanco D (2018) Theoricity, observation and homology: a response to Pearson. Hist Philos Life Sci 40:42

    Google Scholar 

  • Saint-Hilaire ÉG (1830) Principes de philosophie zoologique. Pichon et Didier, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Sereno PC (2007) Logical basis for morphological characters in phylogenetics. Cladistics 23:565–587

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon C, Frati F, Beckenbach A et al (1994) Evolution, weighting, and phylogenetic utility of mitochondrial gene sequences and a compilation of conserved polymerase chain reaction primers. Ann Entomol Soc Am 87:651–701

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson GG (1961) Principles of animal taxonomy. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1988) Reconstructing the past: parsimony, evolution, and inference. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogt L (2018) Towards a semantic approach to numerical tree inference in phylogenetics. Cladistics 34:200–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (1996) Optimization alignment: the end of multiple sequence alignment in phylogenetics? Cladistics 12:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (1999) Fixed character states and the optimization of molecular sequence data. Cladistics 15:379–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2001a) Homology and DNA sequence data. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, New York, pp 303–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2001b) Homology and the optimization of DNA sequence data. Cladistics 17:S3–S11

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2002) Optimization alignment: down, up, error, and improvements. In: DeSalle R, Giribet G, Wheeler WC (eds) Techniques in molecular systematics and evolution. Birkhäuser, Basel, pp 55–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2003a) Iterative pass optimization of sequence data. Cladistics 19:254–260

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2003b) Search-based optimization. Cladistics 19:348–355

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2003c) Implied alignment: a synapomorphy-based multiple-sequence alignment method and its use in cladogram search. Cladistics 19:261–268

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (2006) Dynamic homology and the likelihood criterion. Cladistics 22:157–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC, Aagesen L, Arango CP et al (2006) Dynamic homology and phylogenetic systematics: a unified approach using POY. American Museum of Natural History, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC, Lucaroni N, Hong L et al (2015) POY version 5: phylogenetic analysis using dynamic homologies under multiple optimality criteria. Cladistics 31:189–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO (1979) Cladograms and phylogenetic trees. Syst Zool 28:88–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO, Lieberman BS (2011) Phylogenetics: theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu X, Clark JM, Mo J et al (2009) A Jurassic ceratosaur from China helps clarify avian digital homologies. Nature 459:940–944

    Google Scholar 

  • Young RL, Wagner GP (2011) Why ontogenetic homology criteria can be misleading: lessons from digit identity transformations. J Exp Zoolog B Mol Dev Evol 316B:165–170

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Martín Ramírez and three anonymous reviewers for commenting on an earlier version of the manuscript. This work has been funded by the research Projects PUNQ 1401/15 and SAI 827-223/19 (Universidad Nacional de Quilmes, Argentina), UNTREF 32/15 255 (Universidad Nacional Tres de Febrero, Argentina) and UBACyT 20020170200106BA (Universidad de Buenos Aires, Argentina).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ariel Jonathan Roffé.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Roffé, A.J. Dynamic homology and circularity in cladistic analysis. Biol Philos 35, 21 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-9737-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-9737-4

Keywords

Navigation