Skip to main content
Log in

Rethinking Right: Moral Epistemology in Management Research

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most management researchers pause at the threshold of objective right and wrong. Their hesitation is understandable. Values imply a “subjective,” personal dimension, one that can invite religious and moral interference in research. The dominant epistemological camps of positivism and subjectivism in management stumble over the notion of moral objectivity. Empirical research can study values in human behavior, but hard-headed scientists should not assume that one value can be objectively better than another. In this article, we invite management researchers to rethink this presumption. We show how accepting at least a limited form of moral objectivity, namely, an epistemic orientation that seeks objective moral reasons, can benefit management research by 1. guiding research practice; 2. using patterns of moral objectivity as clues for formulating empirical hypotheses for psychological explanations; and 3. adding prescriptive power to empirical theories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, we follow standard practice in moral philosophy and use the terms “ethics” and “morality” as synonyms. We acknowledge that, however, Aristotelians sometimes use the two terms often differently, where “ethics” primarily concerns the issue of “What is it for a life to go well?” and “morality,” in contrast, concerns issues such as “What do we owe to each other?”.

  2. By “epistemic” we refer to the structure of knowledge or its justification.

  3. The moral reasoning, however, may make reference to empirical or “natural” states of affairs, as with Aristotle (1962).

  4. According to some theorists, subjective reasons can be “causes” of intentional action (Davidson 1963). For more philosophical discussions about the distinction between objective and subjective reasons, see Harman (2015) and Sepielli (Forthcoming).

  5. In this article, we do not defend a particular view of moral objectivity, an activity already undertaken by several moral philosophers (e.g., Enoch 2011; Scanlon 2014; Setiya 2015; Skorupski 2010). One widely accepted account of moral objectivity is “reflective equilibrium” (Goodman 1955; Rawls 1971). Reflective equilibrium represents an attempt to justify moral values by achieving a state of coherence in a dynamic process of reasoning, which involves moving back and forth between, on the one hand, (a) considered moral judgments and (b) relevant background theories (Daniels 1996; Bambrough 1979; DePaul 1993; McMahan 2004). It works back and forth between (a) and (b), making incremental adjustments to existing beliefs about cases and particular principles in the light of background theories, and then moves to the other side, making incremental adjustments to theories in light of moral intuitions. The culmination of the reasoning process is an equilibrium point where incremental change is no longer necessary. The underlying idea behind reflective equilibrium is that rational and informed people’s substantive convergence can be an important proxy for moral objectivity. But as Rawls himself points out, convergence is not itself moral objectivity. Note that divergence of normative views by itself does not refute moral objectivity. First, rational disagreement can exist even when discussing empirical fact (McMahon 2009). Second, the fact that reflective equilibrium cannot explain how to fundamentally resolve a genuine moral conflict should not be considered a defect. Any adequate theory must reflect rather than dissolve conflicts if intrinsically difficult. Third, the moral skepticism based on divergence itself assumes a certain moral objectivity because the critic purports the criticism to be objectively true. For more comprehensive discussions about this matter, see McGrath (2010).

  6. Normative ethical relativism is typically distinguished from metaethical relativism. The latter deals primarily with the epistemic basis for moral judgments rather than the objective status of the judgments themselves. Metaethical relativism, in contrast to normative ethical relativism, is frequently defended by moral philosophers.

  7. Deception is not always unethical. For circumstances under which deception can be unethical, see, for example, Strudler (2005).

  8. The positivist and the subjectivist division can be articulated in much greater detail, and the division itself is open to challenge, especially by philosophers of science. For the purposes of this article, however, we accept the simple division. It is one commonly made by management scholars.

  9. At this point, one might note a possible difference between management research and moral reasoning, asking whether or not, in the domain of moral propositions, there exist what David Armstrong calls “truth makers”—“something in the world which makes it the case that serves as an ontological ground, for this truth.” (1997: p. 155). Social scientists, both positivists and subjectivists, assume that truth makers, such as stock values, currency changes, job stress, or motivation exist, but different camps have different views about what they can know about the facts. A certain version of moral objectivity, especially that of some correspondence theorists (e.g., Boyd 1988; Shafer-Landau 2003), is committed to the view that there must exist truth-makers for moral propositions, and they attempt to explain the existence of moral facts using metaphysics or evolutionary biology. But, more recently, important moral realists (e.g., Scanlon 2014); Setiya 2015) argue that even without truth-makers, moral propositions can be objectively true or false.

  10. Most but not all moral philosophers accept moral objectivity. For instance, those who hold expressivism (Blackburn 1984; Gibbard 1990) hold that moral value statements are simply expressions of one’s noncognitive attitudes, such as personal approval or disapproval. But the expressivist has several difficult problems to solve. One of them is the Geach-Frege problem (Geach 1960; Searle 1962), which has stubbornly resisted solution from anti-objectivist positions (Drier 1996; Sinnott-Armstrong 2000). Today, most current anti-objectivists have softened their views (See van Roojen 2009, for reviews). Contemporary anti-objectivists accept, at least, the epistemic features of moral objectivism (Blackburn 1984; Gibbard 1990).

  11. For more philosophical discussion about the objective status of moral knowledge, see Boyd (1988), Brink (1989), Enoch (2011), Hampton (2012), Scanlon (2014), Setiya (2015), Skorupski (2010), Smith (1994), Shafer-Landau (2003).

  12. More metaphysical discussion about how moral deliberation, acceptance of moral mistake, and correction can philosophically demonstrate objectivity of moral propositions can be found in Brink (1989).

  13. One can argue that values about how research ought to be done can be reduced to usefulness. First, usefulness is itself a value, rather than an empirical fact, since what is useful is based on a more fundamental value like well-being. Second, what is true is not always equivalent to what is useful. In some contexts, a scientifically untrue theory or story may be more pragmatically useful than a true theory. Indeed, Alvin Plantinga (1993) argues that epistemic values cannot be well explained by evolutionary biology or survival alone, in part because untrue stories can sometimes benefit our survival better than true stories.

  14. This quote is from an unpublished manuscript (De los Reyes, Kim and Weaver, Unpublished).

  15. This view, interestingly enough, is similar to the one defended by the so-called school of moral realism in moral philosophy (e.g., Scanlon 2014; Setiya 2015).

  16. Another example is Gino and Pierce’s (2009) study about “unethical” behavior. In one experiment, when piles of cash (about $7000 in real $1 bills) were present on a table before participants, the participants were more likely to behave unethically—to cheat—on the task than when less money (only the cash necessary to pay participants) was visually available. Note that what the authors want to explain is the nature of a certain “unethical” behavior—not merely behavior that the subjects perceive as unethical. This follows from the fact that their hypothesis is that “the presence of abundant wealth increases the likelihood of individuals to behave unethically for personal gain” (p. 143). Therefore, the experiment suggests that cheating in the experiment is an “objectively unethical” behavior. Again, by treating the concept of cheating as a “thick” or hybrid concept, the experiment can be interpreted as relevant to the general question of how people ought, objectively, to behave.

  17. In fact, the GSIA (Graduate School of Industrial Administration) of Carnegie Institute of Technology—the former name of the Tepper School of Business, Carnegie Mellon University, was one of the earliest business schools that incorporated ethics into a curriculum (Modzelewski 2001). Ethics has been taught at the GSIA and the Tepper School since 1966—one year before the publication of Simon’s article (Simon 1967).

References

  • Abend, G. (2010). What’s new and what’s old about the new sociology of morality. In S. Hitlin & S. Valsey (Eds.), Handbook of the sociology of morality. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvesson, M., & Willmott, H. (1992). On the idea of emancipation in management and organization studies. Academy of Management Review, 17, 432–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvesson, M., & Willmott, H. (2012). Making sense of management. London, UK: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alzola, M. (2015). Virtuous persons and virtuous actions in business ethics and organizational research. Business Ethics Quarterly, Online First.

  • Andreas, W. F. (2004). When in Rome… moral maturity and ethics for international economic organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 54, 17–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariely, D. (2008). Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions (1st ed.). New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1962). Nicomachean ethics (M. Ostwald, Trans.). New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

  • Asher, C. C., Mahoney, J. M., & Mahoney, J. T. (2005). Towards a property rights foundation for a stakeholder theory of the firm. Journal of Management and Governance, 9, 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astley, W. (1985). Administrative science as socially constructed truth. Administrative Science Quarterly, 30, 497–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astley, W., & Zammuto, R. F. (1992). Organization science, managers, and language games. Organization Science, 3, 443–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillie, J., & Meckler, M. R. (2012). Truth and objectivity regained. Journal of Management Inquiry, 21, 248–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bambrough, R. (1979). Moral skepticism and moral knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, J. C. (2014). European and north American approaches to organizations and strategy research: An Atlantic divide? Not. Organization Science, 22, 1164–1679.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Z. (1989). Modernity and the holocaust. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M. H., & Tenbrunsel, A. E. (2011). Blind spots: Why we fail to do what’s right and what to do about it. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M. H., & Watkins, M. (2004). Predictable surprises: The disasters you should have seen coming, and how to prevent them. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechara, J. P., & Van de Ven, A. H. (2007). Philosophy of science underlying engaged scholarship. In A. H. Van de Ven (Ed.), Engaged scholarship: A guide for organizational and social research. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the word. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice (R. Nice, Trans.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice (R. Nice, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  • Boyd, R. N. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. (1967). Ethical relativism. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopedia of philosophy. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burrell, G. (1997). Organization paradigms. In A. Sorge & M. Warner (Eds.), The handbook of organization behavior. London: International Thompson Business Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, L. A. (1999). Raising the stakes in the ultimatum game: Experimental evidence from indonesia. Economic Inquiry, 37, 47–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Hardie, J. (2012). Evidence-based policy: A practical guide to do it better. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coff, R. W. (1999). When competitive advantage doesn’t lead to performance: The resource-based view and stakeholder bargaining power. Organization Science, 10, 119–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, T. R. (2014). Moral chacracter in the workplace. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 107, 943–963.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cropanzano, R., Goldman, B., & Folger, R. (2003). Deontic justice: The role of moral principles in workplace fairness. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 8, 1019–1024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalton, D. D., Daily, C. M., Certo, S. T., & Roengpitya, R. (2003). Meta-analysis of financial performance and quality: Fusion or confusion? Academy of Management Journal, 46, 13–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalton, D. D., Daily, C. M., Johnson, J. L., & Ellstrand, A. E. (1999). Number of directions and financial performance: A meta-analysis. Academy of Management Journal, 42, 674–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1996). Justice and justification. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 60, 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27, 314–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1991). Three varieties of knowledge’. In A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), A. J Ayer memorial essays: Royal institute of philosophy supplement, vol. 30. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Deetz, S. (2009). Organizational research as alternative ways of attending to and talking about structures and activities. In D. Buchanan & A. Bryman (Eds.), The sage handbook of organizational research methods. London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • De los Reyes, G., Kim, T. W., & Weaver, G. (Unpublished). Teaching ethics in business schools: A conversation on disciplinary differences, academic provincialism, and the case for integrated pedagogy.

  • DeHaan, C. R., Hirai, T., & Ryan R. M. (2015). Nussbaum’s capabilities and self-determination theory’s basic psychological needs: Relating some fundamentals of human wellness. Journal of Happiness Studies, Online first.

  • DePaul, M. R. (1993). Balance and refinement. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, L. (1985). In defense of organization theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (1994). When integration fails: The logic of prescription and description in business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 157–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, L. (2003). Organization theory as a positive science. In H. Tsoukas & C. Knudsen (Eds.), The oxford handbook of organization theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, L. (2005). For positive management theories while retaining science: Reply to Ghoshal. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4, 109–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (2012). The epistemic fault line in corporate governance. Academy of Management Review, 37, 256–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., & Preston, L. E. (1995). The stakeholder theory of the corporate concepts, evidence, and implications. Academy of Management Review, 20, 65–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., & Walsh, J. P. (2015). Toward a theory of business. Research in Organizational Behavior. doi:10.1016/j.riob.2015.10.002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. (2002). Lack of Character: Personality and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drier, J. (1996). Expressivist embeddings and minimalist truth. Philosophical Studies, 83, 29–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1975). Hard cases. Harvard Law Review, 88, 1057–1109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1977). Taking rights serisouly. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1984). Rights as trumps. In J. Waldron (Ed.), Theories of rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1986). Law’s empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1996). Objectivity and truth: You’d better believe it. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 25, 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterby-Smith, M., Thrope, R., & Jackson, P. (2012). Management research. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, J. R., & Rothbard, N. P. (1999). Work and family stress and well-being: An examination of person–environment fit in the work and family domains. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 77, 85–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ezzamel, M., & Willmott, H. (2014). Registering ‘the ethical’ in organization theory formation: Toward the disclosure of an ‘invisible’ force. Organization Studies, 35, 1013–1039.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabian, F. H. (2000). Keeping the tension: Pressures to keep the controversy in the management discipline. Academy of Management Review, 25, 350–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1992). In defense of moral rights. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 12, 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, M. S., & Orlikowski, W. J. (2011). Theorizing practice and practicing theory. Organization Science, 22, 1240–1253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Folger, R., & Salvador, R. (2008). Is management theory too “self-ish”? Journal of Management, 34, 1127–1151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterl, y, 4, 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (2000). Business ethics at the millennium. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10, 169–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1960). Ascriptivism. Philosophical Review, 69, 221–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S. (2005). Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4, 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S., & Moran, P. (1996). Bad for practice: A critique of the transaction cost theory. Academy of Management Review, 21, 13–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1986). The constitutions of society. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., & Ariely, D. (2012). The dark side of creativity: Original thinkers can be more dishonest. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102(445), 459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., Ayal, S., & Ariely, D. (2013). Self-serving altruism? The lure of unethical actions that benefit others. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 93, 285–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., & Pierce, L. (2009). The abundance effect: Unethical behavior in the presence of wealth. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 109, 142–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gioia, D. A. (2003). Give it up: Reflections on the interpreted world. Journal of Management Inquiry, 12, 285–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guillen, M. (2001). The limits of convergence: Globalization and organizational change in Argentina, South Korea, and Spain. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. E. (2012). The authority of reason. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (2002). No character or personality. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13, 87–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2015). The irrelevance of moral ignorance. In Russ Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 10). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassard, J., & Kelemen, M. (2002). Production and consumption in organization knowledge. Organization, 9, 331–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, A. (2015). Scorpions, cockroaches and the reality of unpleasant leaders, Financial Times: September 9. London: FT.Com.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollensbe, E., Wookey, C., Hickey, L., George, G., & Nichols, V. (2014). Organizations with purpose. Academy of Management Journal, 57, 1227–1234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, J. (2010). Business ethics as rational choice. Boston: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, S. D. (2004). For truth and realism in management research. Journal of Management Inquiry, 20, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • John, P., & Duberley, J. (2000). Understanding management research: An introduction to epistemology. London: Sage.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T. M. (1991). Ethical decision making by individuals in organizations: An issue-contingent model. Academy of Management Review, 16, 366–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. (1986). Fairness as a constraint on profit seeking: Entitlements in the market. American Economic Review, 76, 728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeley, M. (1983). Values in organizational theory and management education. Academy of Management Review, 8, 376–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khurana, R., & Spender, J. C. (2012). Herbert A. Simon on what ails business schools: More than ‘a problem in organizational design’. Journal of Management Studies, 49, 619–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1973). The claim to moral adequacy of highest stage of moral judgement. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 630–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on moral development (1st ed.). San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1984). Scientifc realism. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, J. T., & Kor, Y. (2015). Advancing the human capital perspective on value creation by joining capabilities and governance approach. Academy of Management Perspectives, Online First.

  • Mantere, S., & Ketokivi, M. (2013). Reasoning in organization science. Academy of Management Review, 38, 70–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. (2010). Moral realism without convergence. Philosophical Topics, 38, 59–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2004). Moral intuition. In H. LaFollette (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to ethical theory. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, C. (2009). Reasonable disagreement: A theory of morality. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2003). The challenge of humanistic management. Journal of Business Ethics, 44, 77–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messick, S. (1980). Test validity and the ethics of assessment. American Psychologist, 35, 1012–1027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messick, S. (1989). Meaning and values in test validation: The science and ethics of assessment. Educational Researcher, 18, 5–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messick, S. (1995). Validity of psychological assessment. American Psychologist, 50, 741–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, S. (1963). Behavioral study of obedience. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 67(4), 371–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitroff, I. I. (1972). The myth of objectivity or why science needs a new psychology of science. Management Science, 18, 613–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modzelewski, E. (2001). CMU’s Tom Kerr retiring after teaching business ethics for 35 years. Post-Gazette, April 17.

  • Moldoveanu, M. C., & Baum, J. A. (2005). Contemporary debates in organizational epistemology. In J. A. Baum (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to organizations. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Academy of Sciences. (2009). On being a scientist: A guide to responsible conduct in research. Washington, D.C.: The National Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nystrom, P. C., & Starbuck, W. H. (1977). Why prescription is prescribed. TIMS Studies in Management Studies, 5, 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrow, C. (1986). Complex organizations: A critical essay. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeffer, J. (2015). Leadership BS: Fixing workplaces and careers one truth at a time. New York: Harper Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, L. E. (1986). Business and public policy. Journal of Management, 12, 261–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2002). The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, D. P., & Jones, T. M. (1995). An agent morality view of business policy. Academy of Management Review, 20, 22–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risen, J. (2015). Psychologists approve ban on role in national security interrogations, New York Times: August 7.

  • Robertson, D. (1993). Empiricism in business ethics: Suggested research directions. Journal of Business Ethics, 12(8), 585–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Root, J. (1991). Philosophy of social science. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2012). Philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg, J. (2008). Understanding the separation thesis. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18, 213–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schatzki, T. R. (2002). The site of the social: A philosophical account of the constitution of social life and change. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a Political Conception of Corporate Responsibility: Business and Society Seen from a Habermasian Perspective. The Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120. doi:10.2307/20159358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1962). Meaning and speech acts. Philosophical Review, 71, 423–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sepielli, A. (Forthcoming). Subjective and objective reasons. In Daniel Star (Ed.), Oxford handbook of reasons and normativity. Oxford University Press.

  • Setiya, K. (2015). Knowing right from wrong. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, C., & Challenger, R. (2013). Revisting paradigm(s) in management research: A rhetorical analysis of the paradigm wars. International Journal of Management Reviews, 15, 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1957). Administrative behavior. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1967). The business school: A problem in organizational design. Journal of Management Studies, 4, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1977). Models of discovery: And other topics in the methods of science. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2000). Expressivism and embedding. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 677–693.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sison, A. J. G. (2014). Happiness and virtue ethics in business: The ultimate value proposition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski, J. (2010). The domain of reasons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective: Selected essays in epistemology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M., & Sosa, E. (2005). Contemporary debates in epistemology. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strudler, A. (2005). Deception unraveled. Journal of Philosophy, 102(9), 458–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suchman, M. C. (1995). Managing legitimacy: Strategic and institutional approaches. Academy of Management Review, 20, 571–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, D. L. (1999). Toward an integrative theory of business and society: A research strategy for corporate social performance. Academy of Management Review, 24, 506–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenbrunsel, A. E., & Smith-Crown, K. (2008). Ethical decision-making: Where we’ve been and where we’re going. In J. P. Walsh & A. P. Brief (Eds.), Academy of Management Annals, 2 (pp. 545–607). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1990). The realm of rights. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treviño, L. K., & Weaver, G. R. (1994). Business ETHICS/BUSINESS ethics: One field or two? Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 113–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treviño, L. K., Weaver, G. R., & Reynolds, S. J. (2006). Behavioral ethics in organizations: A review. Journal of Management, 32, 951–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsui, A. S. (2013). The spirit of science and socially responsible scholarship. Management and Organization Review, 9, 375–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Maanen, J. (1995a). Fear and loathing in organization studies. Organization Science, 6, 687–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Maanen, J. (1995b). Style as theory. Organization Science, 6, 133–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (Ed.). (1984). Theories of rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weaver, G. R., Reynolds, S. J., & Brown, M. E. (2014). Moral intuition: Connecting current knowledge to future organizational research and practice. Journal of Management, 40, 100–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weick, K. E. (1979). The social psychology of organizing. New York: Addison Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weick, K. E. (1995). Sensemaking in organizations. Nebury Park: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. (1963). The ethical implications of cultural relativity. Journal of Philosophy, 60, 169–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2005). The nature of rights. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33, 223–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2008). The analysis of rights. In M. Kramer, C. Grant, B. Colburn, & A. Hatzistavrou (Eds.), The legacy of H.L.A. Hart. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. H. (1994). The normative/descriptive distinction in methodologies of business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 175–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, J. D. (1999). Collaboration in the boardroom: Behavioral and performance consequences of CEO-board social ties. Academy of Management Journal, 42(1), 7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westwood, R., & Clegg, S. (2002). Debating organization: Point-counterpoint in organization studies. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicks, A. C. (1996). Overcoming the separation thesis: The need for a reconsideration of business and society research. Business and Society, 35, 89–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicks, A. C., & Freeman, R. (1998). Organization studies and the new pragmatism: Positivism, anti-positivism, and the search for ethics. Organization Science, 9, 123–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • William, J. 1975 (1907). Pragmatism: A new name for some old ways of thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (2005). The economics of governance. American Economic Review, 95, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • York, J. G., Sarasvathy, S. D., & Wicks, A. (2013). An entrepreneurial perspective on value creation in public-private ventures. Academy of Management Review, 35, 307–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zajac, E. J., & Westphal, J. D. (1994). The costs and benefits of managerial incentives and monitoring in large U.S. corporations: When is more not better? Strategic Management Journal, 15, 121–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zald, M. N. (1991). Sociology as a discipline: Quasi-science and quasi-humanities (pp. 165–187). Fall/Winter: The American Sociologist.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zald, M. N. (1993). Organization studies as a scientific and humanistic enterprise: Toward a reconceptualiza. Organization Science, 4, 513–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimbardo, P. G. (1971). The power and pathology of imprisonment. Congressional Record. (Serial No. 15, October 25, 1971). Hearings before Subcommittee No. 3, of the Committee on the Judiciary, House of Representatives, 92nd Congress, First Session on Corrections, Part II, Prisons, Prison Reform and Prisoners’ Rights: California. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.

  • Zingales, L. (2000). In search of new foundations. Journal of Finance, 55, 1623–1653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tae Wan Kim.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kim, T.W., Donaldson, T. Rethinking Right: Moral Epistemology in Management Research. J Bus Ethics 148, 5–20 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-3009-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-015-3009-2

Keywords

Navigation