Skip to main content
Log in

International Environmental Agreements: The Case of Costly Monetary Transfers

  • Published:
Environmental and Resource Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most existing international environmental agreements to resolve transboundary pollution problems appear constrained in the sense that either monetary transfers accompany uniform abatement standards (agreements based on a uniform standard with monetary transfers), or differentiated abatement standards are established, but without monetary transfers (agreements based on differentiated standards). For two asymmetric countries facing the challenge of a transboundary pollution problem, we compare the relative efficiency of these two second-best agreements. We study especially the role of the costs associated with transfer payments across countries in the choice of these agreements. To conduct this analysis, we use a negotiation game and the generalized Nash bargaining solution (Nash in Econometrica 21:128–140, 1953) as the equilibrium. For total welfare, our findings show that countries collectively prefer the uniform to the differentiated agreement if the cost of transfers is sufficiently low compared to the ratio for countries of the difference of the abatement costs between the two agreements. In the analysis of individual welfare, we also discuss the reluctance of one country to sign a specific type of agreement even if it is better off than in the case of non-cooperation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Our aim is to compare the welfare related to these two agreements, not to explain why these arrangements emerge.

  2. The term ‘uniform standard’ could potentially be misleading. A more appropriate term would be ‘equiproportional emissions reductions’; however, for simplicity we use uniform standard to underline the contrast with ‘differentiated standards’.

  3. The Stockholm Convention on Persistent Organic Pollutants, signed in 2001, is another example of a UT agreement.

  4. Several papers study environmental problems in a cooperative bargaining framework, such as the Nash bargaining solution: see among others Hoel (1991); Carraro and Siniscalco (1993); Buchholz et al. (2005). However, to take account of the dynamic process of bargaining, negotiations can be modelled by non-cooperative bargaining games. Work on environmental problems includes, among others, Chen (1997); Compte and Jéhiel (1997); Caparros et al. (2004); Courtois and Tazdait (2014).

  5. Bayramoglu and Jacques (2012) conduct a similar analysis in the case of a quasi-linear utility function, with a concave benefit function from global abatement and a linear abatement cost function. However, the non-linear case is able to highlight cases where one of the countries is reluctant to sign a specific type of agreement, even if it is better off than in the case of non-cooperation.

  6. In our model, individual welfare is the level of utility for each country, which can be written either as the sum of the benefits from global abatement and the consumption of a private good, or the sum of the benefits from global abatement and exogenous initial endowments, minus abatement costs.

  7. \(\Omega _{i}\) can be considered an initial endowment of labor, which plays the role of the numeraire. The production of the good is then achieved with a ‘one to one’ technology (1 unit of input implies 1 unit of production).

  8. Agreement U refers to an agreement based on a uniform standard without transfers, and agreement DT refers to an agreement based on differentiated standards with transfers.

  9. In this paper, we do not try to explain why countries do not agree on the first-best agreement, namely the DT agreement. In a model with informational problems, we could assume that the first-best agreement is costly to implement because of the high negotiation costs associated with multiple negotiation variables. See e.g. Endres (1996); Harstad (2007).

  10. To introduce monetary transfer payments requires the assumption that the marginal utility for money is constant.

  11. Here, we assume for simplicity that the degree of imperfection of transfers is exogenous. This cost could become endogenous in a political economy model. In that framework, this cost could be related to the rent that the donor country should pay to national lobbies to convince them to make transfer payments to another country. Another possibility would be that the cost is related to the degree of corruption in the recipient country. For a review of the literature on the political economy of IEAs, see Wangler (2011).

  12. This condition is verified for the example presented in “Positivity of transfers in the UT agreement: the case with a linear cost, and \(\alpha \simeq 0, \delta <1, \gamma =1/2\) (Condition C1)” in Appendix .

  13. When transfers are null, the differentiated agreement dominates the uniform agreement in terms of welfare. In that case, the comparison is obvious.

  14. In the quasi-linear case, this analysis has been conducted using the Pareto frontier (Bayramoglu and Jacques 2012). In the case of a non-linear cost function, we cannot use the Pareto frontier which becomes non-linear and, thus, difficult to handle analytically. However, interpretation of the results in both the linear and non-linear cases is very similar.

  15. If Conditions C3 and C4 aresatisfied, this condition always holds (see the proof of Proposition 5 in “Appendix” ).

  16. This terminology is taken from Petrakis and Xepapadeas (1996).

  17. http://www.climate-policy-watcher.org/?q=node/584.

References

  • Barrett S (1994) Self-enforcing international environmental agreements. Oxf Econ Pap 46:878–894

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett S (2001) International cooperation for sale. Eur Econ Rev 45:1835–1850

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayramoglu B, Jacques J-F (2011) The role of fixed cost in international environmental negotiations. Environ Dev Econ 16(2):221–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayramoglu B, Jacques J-F (2012) Les négociations internationales sur l’environnement: norme uniforme et normes différenci ées. Rev Econ Polit 122(6):943–969

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt U-S (2004) Are uniform solutions focal?—The case of international environmental agreements. Environ Resour Econ 25:357–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz W, Haupt A, Peters W (2005) International environmental agreements and strategic voting. Scand J Econ 107(1):175–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Businessgreen (2010) Cancun Green Fund to dominate global climate finance, James Murray, 13 December 2010

  • Caparros A, Péreau J-C, Tazdait T (2004) North–South climate change negotiations: a sequential game with asymmetric information. Public Choice 121:455–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carraro C, Siniscalco D (1993) Strategies for the international protection of the environment. J Public Econ 52:309–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chander P, Tulkens H (1995) A core-theoretic solution for the design of cooperative agreements on transfrontier pollution. Int Tax Public Financ 2:279–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chander P, Tulkens H (1997) The core of an economy with multilateral environmental externalities. Int J Game Theory 26:379–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen Z (1997) Negotiating an agreement on global warming: a theoretical analysis. J Environ Econ Manag 32:170–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Compte O, Jéhiel P (1997) International negotiations and dispute resolution mechanisms: the case of environmental negotiations. In: Carraro C (ed) International environmental negotiations: strategic policy issues. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland B, Taylor S (2005) Free trade and global warming: a trade theory view of the Kyoto protocol. J Environ Econ Manag 49:205–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courtois P, Tazdait T (2014) Bargaining over a climate deal: deadline and delay. Ann Oper Res 220(4):205–221

  • Dannenberg A, Lange A, Sturm B (2010) On the formation of coalitions to provide public goods—experimental evidence from the lab. NBER working paper series, working paper 15967

  • Endres A (1996) Designing a greenhouse treaty: some economic problems. In: Eide E, van der Bregh R (eds) Law and economics of the environment. Jurudisk Forlag, Oslo, pp 201–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Endres A (1997) Negotiating a climate convention: the role of prices and quantities. Int Rev Law Econ 17:147–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eyckmans J (1999) Strategy proof uniform effort sharing schemes for transfrontier pollution problems. Environ Resour Econ 14:165–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finus M, Rundshagen B (1998) Toward a positive theory of coalition formation and endogenous instrumental choice in global pollution control. Public Choice 96:145–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finus M (2001) Game theory and international environmental cooperation. Edwar Elgar Inc, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finus M (2008) Game theoretic research on the design of international environmental agreements: insights, critical remarks, and future challenges. Int Rev Environ Resour Econ 2:29–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuentes-Albero C, Rubio S (2010) Can international environmental cooperation be bought? Eur J Oper Res 202:255–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harstad B (2007) Harmonization and side payments in political cooperation. Am Econ Rev 97:871–889

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoel M (1991) Global environmental problems: the effects of unilateral actions taken by one country. J Environ Econ Manag 20:55–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoel M (1992) International environment conventions: the case of uniform reductions of emissions. Environ Resour Econ 2:141–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Jéhiel P (1997) Bargaining between benevolent jurisdictions or when delegation induces inefficiencies. J Public Econ 65:61–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larson BA, Tobey JA (1994) Uncertain climate change and the international policy response. Ecol Econ 11:77–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luken R, Grof T (2006) The Montreal Protocol’s multilateral fund and sustainable development. Ecol Econ 56(2):241–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maler K-G (1989) The acid rain game. In: Folmer H, Van Ierland E (eds) Valuation methods and policy making in environmental economics. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 231–251

    Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell A, Whinston MD, Green JR (1995) Microeconomic theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash JF (1953) Two-person cooperative games. Econometrica 21:128–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newbery D-M (1990) Acid rain. Econ Policy 5:297–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrakis E, Xepapadeas A (1996) Environmental consciousness and moral hazard in international agreements to protect the environment. J Public Econ 60:95–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wangler L, Altamirano-Cabrera J-C, Weikard H-P (2011) The political economy of international environmental agreements: a survey. JENA Economic Research Papers 2011–038. Jena, Germany

  • Weikard HP (2009) Cartel stability under optimal sharing rule. Manch Sch 77:575–593

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Basak Bayramoglu.

Additional information

We are grateful to Bernard Caillaud for the motivation of the paper, and to Ivar Ekeland for his invitation to the University British Columbia (UBC) where the research has been started. We would like to thank Brian Copeland, Philippe Bernard, Françoise Forges and two referees for their constructive remarks. We would also like to thank the participants of the EURiSCO seminar at Université Paris Dauphine, Paris (June 2006), the Third World Congress of Environmental and Resource Economists, Kyoto (July 2006), and the PGPPE Workshop, Marseille (April 2007).

Appendices

Appendix 1: Nash Equilibrium

1.1 Proof of Lemma 1

The objective of country 1 is to maximize its utility function with respect to its budget constraint, taking as given the level of abatement of country \(2, a_{2}: \underset{a_{1}}{Max}[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{1}-C(a_{1})]\).

The first-order condition of this program is the following: \(B^{^{\prime }}(A)=C^{^{\prime }}(a_{1})\). Similarly, the first-order condition of the program for country 2 is the following: \(\alpha B^{^{\prime }}(A)=\delta C^{^{\prime }}(a_{2})\).

1.2 Uniqueness of the Nash Equilibrium

The equilibrium is defined by:

$$\begin{aligned} B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})&= C^{\prime }(a_{1}) \quad \text {(1)} \\ \alpha B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})&= \delta C^{\prime }(a_{2}) \quad \text {(2)} \end{aligned}$$

Suppose there is another equilibrium:

$$\begin{aligned} B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})&= C^{\prime }(\overline{a} _{1}) \quad \text {(3)} \\ \alpha B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})&= \delta C^{\prime }( \overline{a}_{2})\quad \text {(4)} \end{aligned}$$

Assume that \(a_{1}>\overline{a}_{1}\), so \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})>B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\) because of (1) and (3), and the convexity of \(C(.)\). Consequently, \(a_{2}>\overline{a}_{2}\) because of (2) and (4), and the convexity of \(C(.)\). So \(a_{1}+a_{2}>\overline{a}_{1}+ \overline{a}_{2}\), then \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})<B^{\prime }(\overline{a} _{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\) because of the concavity of \(B(.)\), which is contradictory to \(a_{1}>\overline{a}_{1}\) and \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})>B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\).

Assume that \(a_{1}<\overline{a}_{1}\), so \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})<B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\) because of (1) and (3), and the convexity of \(C(.)\). Consequently, \(a_{2}<\overline{a}_{2}\) because of (2) and (4), and the convexity of \(C(.)\). So \(a_{1}+a_{2}<\overline{a}_{1}+ \overline{a}_{2}\), then \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})>B^{\prime }(\overline{a} _{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\) because of the concavity of \(B(.)\), which is contradictory to \(a_{1}<\overline{a}_{1}\) and \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})<B^{\prime }(\overline{a}_{1}+\overline{a}_{2})\).

This proof shows that the Nash equilibrium is unique under the standard assumptions of a concave benefit function and a convex cost function.

Appendix 2: Existence and Uniqueness of the Cooperative Equilibria

1.1 Proof of Proposition 1a

The Pareto optimality results from the following program

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{\overline{a,}t}\text { }NB_{1}&=\max _{\overline{a,}t}\left[ B(2 \overline{a})+c_{1}\right] \\&s.t. \qquad \left\{ \begin{array}{l} \Omega _{1}=c_{1}+C(\overline{a})+(1+\lambda )t \\ \Omega _{2}=c_{2}+\delta C(\overline{a})-t \\ NB_{2}=\alpha B(2\overline{a})+c_{2}\ge \overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

where \(\overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}}\) is exogenous.

If we use the first two constraints, the program becomes

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{\overline{a,}t}\text { }NB_{1}&=\max _{\overline{a,}t}\left[ B(2 \overline{a})+\Omega _{1}-C(\overline{a})-(1+\lambda )t\right] \\&\quad s.t. \qquad NB_{2}=\alpha B(2\overline{a})+\Omega _{2}-\delta C( \overline{a})+t\ge \overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}} \end{aligned}$$

The Lagrangian of this maximization problem is: \(L=[B(2\overline{a})+\Omega _{1}-C(\overline{a})-(1+\lambda )t]+\rho [\alpha B(2\overline{a} )+\Omega _{2}-\delta C(\overline{a})+t-\overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}}]\), where \(\rho \) is the multiplier associated with the constraint.

The first-order conditions (FOCs) with respect to \(\overline{a}\) and \(t\) give:

$$\begin{aligned} 2(\alpha (1+\lambda )+1)B^{\prime }(2\overline{a})=(1+\delta (1+\lambda ))C^{\prime }(\overline{a}) \end{aligned}$$
(11)

The total differential of \(NB_{1}\) is equal to: \(d(NB_{1})=[2B^{\prime }(2 \overline{a})-C^{\prime }(\overline{a})]d\overline{a}-(1+\lambda )dt\), and that of \(NB_{2}\) is equal to: \(d(NB_{2})=[2\alpha B^{\prime }(2\overline{a} )-\delta C^{\prime }(\overline{a})]d\overline{a}+dt\).

On the Pareto frontier, we have

$$\begin{aligned} d(NB_{1})&= \frac{C^{\prime }(\overline{a})(1+\lambda )(\delta -\alpha )}{ (\alpha (1+\lambda )+1)}d\overline{a}-(1+\lambda )dt \\ d(NB_{2})&= \frac{C^{\prime }(\overline{a})(\alpha -\delta )}{(\alpha (1+\lambda )+1)}d\overline{a}+dt \end{aligned}$$

So along the Pareto frontier \(\dfrac{dNB_{1}}{dNB_{2}}=-(1+\lambda )\). Hence, the Pareto frontier is a decreasing line.

1.2 Proof of Proposition 1b

We consider two points on the Pareto frontier. Consider the case where \( \delta C(\overline{a})= \Omega _{2}\) when the private consumption of country 2 and the transfers are both equal to 0. So the point \( (NB_{1,\max },NB_{2,\min })\) defined by \(NB_{1,\max }=B(2\overline{a} )+\Omega _{1}-C(\overline{a})\) and \(NB_{2}=\alpha B(2\overline{a})\) with \( \overline{a}\) defined by \(\delta C(\overline{a})= \Omega _{2}\) is on the Pareto frontier. The point \((NB_{1,\min },NB_{2,\max })\) defined by \( NB_{1,\min }=B(2\overline{a})\) and \(NB_{2,\max }=\alpha B(2\overline{a} )+\Omega _{2}-\delta C(\overline{a})+t\) with \(\overline{a}\) defined by \( 2\alpha B^{\prime }(2\overline{a})=\delta C^{\prime }(\overline{a})\) and \(t\) defined by \((1+\lambda )t+C(\overline{a})=\Omega _{1}\) is also on the Pareto frontier. These two points are different so the Pareto set is not empty.

1.3 Proof of Proposition 1c

The social welfare function is strictly concave and the Pareto set is convex. So there exists a unique bargaining equilibrium for agreement UT.

1.4 Proof of Proposition 2a

The Pareto optimality results from the following program

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{a_{1},a_{2}}\text { }NB_{1}&=\max _{a_{1},a_{2}}\left[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})+c_{1}\right] \\&s.t. \qquad \left\{ \begin{array}{l} \Omega _{1}=c_{1}+C(a_{1}) \\ \Omega _{2}=c_{2}+\delta C(a_{2}) \\ NB_{2}=\alpha B(a_{1}+a_{2})+c_{2}\ge \overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

where \(\overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}}\) is exogenous.

If we use the first two constraints, the program becomes

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{a_{1},a_{2}}\text { }NB_{1}&=\max _{a_{1},a_{2}}\left[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{1}-C(a_{1})\right] \\ s.t. \qquad NB_{2}&=\alpha B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{2}-\delta C(a_{2})\ge \overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}} \end{aligned}$$

The Lagrangian of this maximization problem is: \(L=[B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{1}-C(a_{1})]+\rho [\alpha B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{2}-\delta C(a_{2})-\overset{\overline{-}}{NB_{2}}]\), where \(\rho \) is the multiplier associated with the constraint.

The first-order conditions (FOCs) with respect to \(a_{1}\) and \(a_{2}\) are respectively: \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})-C^{\prime }(a_{1})=-\rho \alpha B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})\), and \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})=-\rho [\alpha B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})-\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})]\).

The ratio of these FOCs gives

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})}=\frac{\alpha }{\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})}+ \frac{1}{C^{\prime }(a_{1})} \end{aligned}$$
(12)

The total differential of \(NB_{1}\) is equal to: \(dNB_{1}=B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})(da_{1}+da_{2})-C^{\prime }(a_{1})da_{1}\), and that of \(NB2\) is equal to: \(dNB_{2}=\alpha B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})(da_{1}+da_{2})-\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})da_{2}\).

On the Pareto frontier, we have

$$\begin{aligned} d(NB_{1})&= \frac{\delta C^{\prime }(a_{1})C^{\prime }(a_{2})}{\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})+\alpha C^{\prime }(a_{1})}(da_{1}+da_{2})-C^{\prime }(a_{1})da_{1} \\ d(NB_{2})&= \frac{\alpha \delta C^{\prime }(a_{1})C^{\prime }(a_{2})}{ \delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})+\alpha C^{\prime }(a_{1})}(da_{1}+da_{2})-\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})da_{2}\\ d(NB_{1})&= \frac{\delta C^{\prime }(a_{1})C^{\prime }(a_{2})da_{2}-\alpha C^{\prime }(a_{1})C^{\prime }(a_{1})da_{1}}{\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})+\alpha C^{\prime }(a_{1})}\\ d(NB_{2})&= \frac{\alpha \delta C^{\prime }(a_{1})C^{\prime }(a_{2})da_{1}-\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})da_{2}}{ \delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})+\alpha C^{\prime }(a_{1})} \end{aligned}$$

Along the Pareto frontier, we have \(\dfrac{dNB_{1}}{dNB_{2}}=-\dfrac{1}{ \delta }\dfrac{C^{\prime }(a_{1})}{C^{\prime }(a_{2})}\). The Pareto frontier is differentiable, thus it is continuous.

1.5 Proof of Proposition 2b

We consider two points on this frontier: for \(NB_{2\text { }}\), consider the case where \(\delta C(a_{2})= \Omega _{2}\) when the private consumption is equal to 0. At that point, the maximum of \(NB_{1\text { }}\)is attainable for \(B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})=C^{\prime }(a_{1})\). So the point \((NB_{1,\max },NB_{2,\min })\) defined by \(NB_{1,\max }=B(a_{1}+\,a_{2})+\Omega _{1}-C(a_{1}) \) and \(NB_{2,\min }=\alpha B(a_{1}+a_{2})\) with \(a_{2}\) defined by \(\delta C(a_{2})= \Omega _{2}\) and \(a_{1}\) defined by \( B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})=C^{\prime }(a_{1})\), is on the Pareto frontier. Similarly, the point \((NB_{1,\min },NB_{2,\max })\) defined by \(NB_{1,\min }=B(a+a_{2})\) and \(NB_{2,\max }=\alpha B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\Omega _{2}-\delta C(a_{2})\) with \(a_{1}\) defined by \(C(a_{1})= \Omega _{1}\) and \(a_{2}\) defined by \(\alpha B^{\prime }(a_{1}+a_{2})=\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2})\) is on the Pareto frontier. So the Pareto set is not empty because these two points are different.

1.6 Proof of Proposition 2c

Assume that there exists an interval \([\underline{NB}_{2},\overline{NB_{2}}]\) on which the Pareto frontier is convex. Consider a point on this interval \( \widetilde{NB}_{2}\) which is a convex combination of \(\underline{NB_{2}}\) and \(\overline{NB_{2}}\), that is, \(\widetilde{NB}_{2}=\gamma \underline{ NB_{2}} +(1-\gamma ) \overline{NB_{2}}\). By definition of the local convexity of the Pareto frontier, the same convex combination of \(NB_{1}\), denoted \(\widetilde{NB}_{1}=\gamma \underline{NB_{1}}+(1-\gamma )\overline{ NB_{1}}\), is greater than the corresponding point \(\widetilde{\widetilde{ NB_{1}}}\) of the Pareto frontier defined by

$$\begin{aligned} \widetilde{\widetilde{NB_{1}}}&= Max\text { }NB_{1} \nonumber \\ s.t.\quad NB_{2}&\ge \text { }\widetilde{NB}_{2}\text { } \end{aligned}$$
(13)

Moreover the concavity of the function \(NB_{1}=B(a_{1}+a_{2})-C(a_{1})+ \Omega _{1}\) implies that \(\widetilde{NB}_{1}=\gamma \underline{NB_{1}} +(1-\gamma )\overline{NB_{1}}<NB_{1}(\gamma \underline{a_{1}}+(1-\gamma ) \overline{a_{1}}, \gamma \underline{a_{2}}+(1-\gamma )\overline{a_{2}})= \overline{\overline{NB_{1}}}\). This level of utility is attainable because \(\overline{\overline{a_{1}}}=\gamma \underline{a_{1}}+(1-\gamma ) \overline{a_{1}}\) and \(\overline{\overline{a_{2}}} =\gamma \underline{a_{2} }+(1-\gamma )\overline{a_{2}}\) are convex combinations of possible abatements in the budget set. Moreover \(\overline{\overline{NB_{2}}}(\gamma \underline{a_{1}}+(1-\gamma )\overline{a_{1}}, \gamma \underline{a_{2}} +(1-\gamma )\overline{a_{2}}) \ge \widetilde{NB}_{2}\) by the concavity of the function \(NB_{2}\). So for the abatements \(\overline{\overline{a_{1}}}\) and \(\overline{\overline{a_{2}}}\) we have \(\overline{\overline{NB_{2}}} \ge \widetilde{NB}_{2}\) and \(\widetilde{\widetilde{NB_{1}}}<\widetilde{ NB}_{1}< \overline{\overline{NB_{1}}}\) which is contradictory with the construction of the Pareto frontier given by program 13, because we have found a level of utility \(\overline{\overline{NB_{1}}}\) associated with a level \(\overline{\overline{NB_{2}}}\) which is above the Pareto frontier. So the Pareto frontier cannot be convex locally. It is concave and the Pareto set is convex.

1.7 Proof of Proposition 2d

The social welfare function is strictly concave and the Pareto set is convex. So there exists a unique bargaining equilibrium for agreement D.

Appendix 3: Total Welfare

The goal of “Appendix”  is to exhibit simple examples which fulfill Conditions C1 and C3.

1.1 Positivity of Transfers in the UT Agreement: The Case with a Linear Cost, and \(\alpha \simeq 0, \delta <1, \gamma =1/2\) (Condition C1)

Here, we assume a linear cost function \(C(a)=ca\), where \(c\) is a positive parameter. We show that when the benefits from global abatement of country 2 are low \((\alpha \simeq 0)\) and the abatement costs of country 2 are lower than that of country 1 \((\delta <1)\), then the transfers from country 1 to country 2 are positive.

For the uniform agreement with transfers from country 1 to country 2, the Nash bargaining problem with equal bargaining powers \((\gamma =1/2)\) leads to the following first-order condition with respect to transfer \((t)\):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \overset{-}{V\text { }}}{\partial t} =0\Longleftrightarrow&-(1+\lambda )\left[ \alpha B(2\overset{-}{a})+\Omega _{2}-\delta c\overset{-}{a}+t-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}\right] \\&+ \left[ B(2\overset{-}{a})+\Omega _{1}-c\overset{-}{a}-(1+\lambda )t-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{1}}\right] =0 \\ \Longleftrightarrow&2(1+\lambda )t=B(2\overset{-}{a})(1-(1+\lambda )\alpha )-(1+\lambda )\Omega _{2}+\Omega _{1}+c\overset{-}{a}((1+\lambda )\delta -1) \\&+((1+\lambda )\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}}) \end{aligned}$$

Concerning the term \(((1+\lambda )\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}})\), the welfare levels at the threat point are given by: \(\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{1}}=B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+\Omega _{1}-cB^{\prime -1}(c)\) and \( \overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}=\alpha B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+\Omega _{2}\). That gives us:

$$\begin{aligned}&((1+\lambda )\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}})=(1+\lambda )(\alpha B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+\Omega _{2}) -B(B^{\prime -1}(c))-\Omega _{1}+cB^{\prime -1}(c) \\&\Longleftrightarrow (1+\lambda )\Omega _{2}-\Omega _{1}+(1+\lambda )\alpha B(B^{\prime -1}(c) -B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+cB^{\prime -1}(c) \end{aligned}$$

We make the following simplifying assumption: \(\alpha \simeq 0\). Then, the level of transfers becomes: \(2(1+\lambda )t\simeq B(2\overset{-}{a})-c \overset{-}{a}(1-(1+\lambda )\delta )-B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+cB^{\prime -1}(c)\).

The expression \(\left[ B(2\overset{-}{a})-c\overset{-}{a}(1-(1+\lambda )\delta )\right] \) is superior or equal to \((NB_{1}-\Omega _{1})\) because \(B(2\overset{-}{a})-c\overset{-}{a}(1-(1+\lambda )\delta )\ge B(2\overset{-}{ a})-c\overset{-}{a}-(1+\lambda )t\). Furthermore, the expression \(\left[ -B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+cB^{\prime -1}(c)\right] \) is equal to \((-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{1}}+\Omega _{1})\). We thus have,

$$\begin{aligned} 2(1+\lambda )t\simeq B(2\overset{-}{a})-c\overset{-}{a}(1-(1+\lambda )\delta )-B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+cB^{\prime -1}(c)\ge NB_{1}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}} \end{aligned}$$

When country 1 signs a UT agreement, its utility is greater than that at the threat point, hence the transfers from country 1 to country 2 are positive.

1.2 The Conditions \(a_{1}\le 1\) and \(a_{2}\ge 0\) (Condition C1)

In order to have \(a_{1}\le 1\) and \(a_{2}\ge 0\), it is sufficient, for instance, that in the case with a linear cost function, we have \(\alpha \simeq 0; (1+\lambda )\delta \simeq 1, (1+\lambda )\delta \) could be less than or greater than 1, in the neighborhood of 1; \(c\) must be sufficiently large and the function \(B^{\prime -1}(.)\) must be sufficiently small.

The second condition of Definition 1 gives us:

$$\begin{aligned} C(a_{1})=C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})+(1+\lambda )t^{*}\Longleftrightarrow ca_{1}=c\overset{-}{a}^{*}+(1+\lambda )t^{*}\Longleftrightarrow a_{1}=\overset{-}{a}^{*}+\frac{(1+\lambda )t^{*}}{c} \end{aligned}$$

Similarly, the first condition of Definition 1 gives:

$$\begin{aligned} a_{2}=2\overset{-}{a}^{*}-a_{1}\Longleftrightarrow a_{2}=2\overset{-}{a} ^{*}-\overset{-}{a}^{*}-\frac{(1+\lambda )t^{*}}{c} \Longleftrightarrow a_{2}=\overset{-}{a}^{*}-\frac{(1+\lambda )t^{*} }{c} \end{aligned}$$

One knows, from proof C1, that the first-order conditions related to the Nash bargaining solution with equal bargaining powers \((\gamma =1/2)\) in the UT agreement imply:

$$\begin{aligned}&(2B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})-c)\left[ \alpha B(2\overset{-}{a} )+\Omega _{2}-\delta c\overset{-}{a}+t-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}\right] \\&+\, (2\alpha B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})-\delta c)(1+\lambda )\left[ \alpha B(2\overset{-}{a})+\Omega _{2}-\delta c\overset{-}{a}+t-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{2}}\right] =0 \\&\Longleftrightarrow (2B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})-c)+(2\alpha B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})-\delta c)(1+\lambda )=0\Longleftrightarrow B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})=\frac{c(1+\delta (1+\lambda ))}{2(1+\alpha (1+\lambda ))} \end{aligned}$$

We make the following assumptions: \(\delta (1+\lambda )\simeq 1\) and \(\alpha \simeq 0\). Under these assumptions, the expression of the marginal benefit becomes \(B^{^{\prime }}(2\overset{-}{a})\simeq c\). This implies the following optimal level of the uniform standard \(\overset{-}{a}\simeq \frac{1 }{2}B^{^{\prime -1}}(c)\), which is positive.

The preceding proof also provides the expression of the transfers when \( \alpha \simeq 0: 2(1+\lambda )t\simeq B(2\overset{-}{a})-c\overset{-}{a} (1-(1+\lambda )\delta )-B(B^{\prime -1}(c))+cB^{\prime -1}(c)\).

If we use the assumption \(\delta (1+\lambda )\simeq 1\) and introduce the expression of the optimal uniform standard, we obtain: \((1+\lambda )t\simeq \frac{1}{2}cB^{\prime -1}(c)\).

Let us return to the study of the levels of differentiated standards \(a_{1}\) and \(a_{2}\).

$$\begin{aligned} a_{1}&= \overset{-}{a}^{*}+\frac{(1+\lambda )t^{*}}{c} \Longleftrightarrow a_{1}=\frac{1}{2}B^{^{\prime -1}}(c)+\frac{1}{2} B^{\prime -1}(c)\Longleftrightarrow a_{1}=B^{^{\prime -1}}(c)\le 1 \\&\text {if }(c)\text { is sufficiently large and }B^{\prime -1}(.)\text { is sufficiently small.} \\ a_{2}&= \overset{-}{a}^{*}-\frac{(1+\lambda )t^{*}}{c} \Longleftrightarrow a_{2}=\frac{1}{2}B^{^{\prime -1}}(c)-\frac{1}{2} B^{\prime -1}(c)\Longleftrightarrow a_{2}=0 \end{aligned}$$

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

The maximum value attainable by the social welfare function in the UT agreement is:

$$\begin{aligned} \overset{-}{V}^{*}=\left[ B(2\overset{-}{a}^{*})-C(\overset{-}{a} ^{*})-(1+\lambda )t^{*}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}}\right] ^{\gamma }\times \left[ \alpha B(2\overset{-}{a}^{*})-\delta C(\overset{-}{a} ^{*})+t^{*}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}\right] ^{1-\gamma } \end{aligned}$$
(14)

This function, if \(\alpha \) is strictly positive, can be written as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\overset{-}{V}^{*}}{\alpha ^{1-\gamma }}\!=\!\left[ B(2\overset{-}{a} ^{*})\!-\!C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})\!-\!(1+\lambda )t^{*}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{ NB_{1}}\right] ^{\gamma }\times \left[ B(2\overset{-}{a}^{*})\!-\!\frac{ \delta }{\alpha }C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})\!+\!\frac{t^{*}}{\alpha }\!-\!\frac{ \overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha }\right] ^{1-\gamma } \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Now we can write the social welfare function with particular values of the differentiated standards:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{V(a_{1},a_{2})}{\alpha ^{1-\gamma }}=\left[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})-C(a_{1})- \overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}}\right] ^{\gamma }\times \left[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})- \frac{\delta }{\alpha }C(a_{2})-\frac{\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha } \right] ^{1-\gamma } \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Notice that the first terms in the brackets in Eqs. 15 and are the same because of Definition 1. Hence, the condition of superiority of the differentiated social welfare function over the uniform becomes:

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ B(a_{1}+a_{2})-\frac{\delta }{\alpha }C(a_{2})-\frac{\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha }\right] ^{1-\gamma }&> \left[ B(2\overset{-}{a}^{*})- \frac{\delta }{\alpha }C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})+\frac{t^{*}}{\alpha }- \frac{\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha }\right] ^{1-\gamma } \end{aligned}$$
(17)
$$\begin{aligned} \Longleftrightarrow \left[ -\delta C(a_{2})\right]&> \left[ -\delta C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})+t^{*}\right] \end{aligned}$$
(18)

because \(B(a_{1}+a_{2})=B(2\overset{-}{a}^{*})\) by Definition 1, \( \alpha \) and \((1-\gamma )\) are positive. From Definition 1, we have \(t^{*}=\frac{C(a_{1})-C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})}{1+\lambda }\). Introducing this expression of transfers into Equation 18, we obtain:

$$\begin{aligned}&\left[ -\delta C(a_{2})\right] > \left[ -\delta C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})+ \frac{C(a_{1})-C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})}{1+\lambda }\right] \end{aligned}$$
(19)
$$\begin{aligned}&\Longleftrightarrow \delta (1+\lambda )\left[ C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})-C(a_{2})\right] > \left[ C(a_{1})-C(\overset{-}{a}^{*})\right] \end{aligned}$$
(20)

From Condition C1 and the first condition of Definition 1, we have \(a_{2}<\overset{-}{a}^{*}<a_{1}\). This implies the positivity of the terms in brackets in Condition 2, say \(\left[ C(\overset{-}{a }^{*})-C(a_{2})\right] >0\) and \(\left[ C(a_{1})-C(\overset{-}{a}^{*}) \right] >0\).

1.4 Superiority of \(a_{1}^{*}\) over \(a_{2}^{*}\) (Condition C3)

Our objective here is to show that \(a_{1}^{*}>a_{2}^{*}\), when the countries have the same bargaining powers \(\gamma =1/2\), and a linear cost function \(C(a)=ca\), where \(c\) is a positive parameter.

The first-order conditions in the D agreement, when \(\gamma =1/2\), are the following:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial V}{\partial a_{1}}\!=\!0&\Longleftrightarrow \frac{\left[ B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!-\!c\right] }{\left[ B(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{1}-ca_{1}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{1}\right] }\!+\!\frac{\left[ \alpha B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\right] }{\left[ \alpha B(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{2}\!-\!\delta ca_{2}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{2}\right] }\!=\!0 \\ \frac{\partial V}{\partial a_{2}}\!=\!0&\Longleftrightarrow \frac{\left[ B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\right] }{\left[ B(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{1}\!-\!ca_{1}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{1}\right] }\!+\!\frac{\left[ \alpha B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})-\delta c\right] }{\left[ \alpha B(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{2}\!-\!\delta ca_{2}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{2}\right] }\!=\!0 \end{aligned}$$

The ratio of these first-order conditions gives us (assuming that we do not divide by 0):

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{cc} &{}\displaystyle \frac{B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2})-c}{B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2})} = \frac{\alpha B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2})}{\alpha B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2})-\delta c} \\ &{} \Longleftrightarrow B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2}) = \frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha }\Longleftrightarrow a_{1}+a_{2}=B^{^{\prime }-1}(\frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha }) \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(21)

If we replace \(B^{^{\prime }}(a_{1}+a_{2})=\frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha }\) in Equation 21, we obtain the following relation: \(U_{2}=\delta U_{1}\) where \(U_{1}\!=\!\left[ B(a_{1}\!+\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{1}\!-\!ca_{1}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB} _{1}\right] \) and \(U_{2}\!=\!\left[ \alpha B(a_{1}\!{+}\!a_{2})\!+\!\Omega _{2}\!-\!\delta ca_{2}\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{N\!B}_{2}\right] \).

We thus have:

$$\begin{aligned} U_{2}\!=\delta U_{1}&\Longleftrightarrow \left[ \alpha B(a_{1}\!+a_{2})\!+\Omega _{2}\!-\delta ca_{2}\!-\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{2}\right] \!=\delta \left[ B(a_{1}\!+a_{2})\!+\Omega _{1}\!-ca_{1}\!-\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{1}\right] \\&\Longleftrightarrow (\delta -\alpha )B(a_{1}+a_{2})+\overset{\wedge }{NB} _{2}-\delta \overset{\wedge }{NB}_{1}=\delta c(a_{1}-a_{2}) \end{aligned}$$

We are interested in whether the term \((\delta -\alpha )B(a_{1}+a_{2})+ \overset{\wedge }{NB}_{2}-\delta \overset{\wedge }{NB}_{1}\) is positive. We replace the expressions of the utility levels at the threat point \(\overset{ \wedge }{NB}_{1}\) and \(\overset{\wedge }{NB}_{2}\) which were calculated above, and obtain:

$$\begin{aligned} (\delta -\alpha )\left[ B(B^{^{\prime }-1}(\frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha } ))-B(B^{\prime -1}(c))\right] +\delta cB^{\prime -1}(c)=\delta c(a_{1}-a_{2}) \end{aligned}$$

We have \(B^{^{\prime }-1}(\frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha })>B^{\prime -1}(c)\) because \(\frac{\delta c}{\delta +\alpha }<c\) and \(B^{^{\prime }-1}(.)\) is a decreasing function. We can conclude then that \(a_{1}^{*}>a_{2}^{*}\) if \(\delta >\alpha \).

1.5 Proof of Proposition 4

The condition of superiority of the social welfare function in the UT agreement over the one in the D agreement \(V^{*}(a_{1}^{*},a_{2}^{*})\) is:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\overset{-}{V}(\overset{-}{a},t)}{\alpha ^{1-\gamma }} \!&= \!\left[ B(2 \overset{-}{a})\!-\!C(\overset{-}{a})\!-\!(1\!+\!\lambda )t\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}} \right] ^{\gamma }\times \left[ B(2\overset{-}{a})\!-\!\frac{\delta }{\alpha }C( \overset{-}{a})\!+\!\frac{t}{\alpha }\!-\!\frac{\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha } \right] ^{1-\gamma } \\ \frac{V^{*}(a_{1}^{*},a_{2}^{*})}{\alpha ^{1-\gamma }} \!&= \!\left[ B(a_{1}^{*}\!+\!a_{2}^{*})\!-\!C(a_{1}^{*})\!-\!\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}} \right] ^{\gamma }\times \left[ B(a_{1}^{*}\!+\!a_{2}^{*})\!-\!\frac{\delta }{\alpha }C(a_{2}^{*})\!-\!\frac{\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}}}{\alpha }\right] ^{1-\gamma }\nonumber \end{aligned}$$
(22)

Notice that the first terms in the brackets in Eq. 22 are the same because of Definition 2. Hence, the condition of superiority of the uniform social welfare function over the differentiated function becomes:

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ -\delta C(\overset{-}{a})+t\right] >\left[ -\delta C(a_{2}^{*}) \right] \end{aligned}$$
(23)

Given Definition 2, we have \(t=\frac{C(a_{1}^{*})-C(\overset{-}{a})}{ (1+\lambda )}\). By introducing this expression of the transfer in Eq. 23, we obtain the result. Condition C3 and the first condition of Definition 2 imply the positivity of the terms in brackets in Condition C4, that is, \(\left[ C(\overset{-}{a})-C(a_{2}^{*}) \right] >0\) and \(\left[ C(a_{1}^{*})-C(\overset{-}{a})\right] >0\).

Appendix 4: Individual Welfare

1.1 Proof of Proposition 5

We begin the proof with a remark. Based on Proposition 2, we know that the social welfare in the UT agreement \(\overline{V}^{*}\) is greater than that in the D agreement \(V^{*}\), if the condition \(\delta (1+\lambda ) [ C(\overset{-}{a})-C(a_{2}^{*})] <[ C(a_{1}^{*})-C( \overset{-}{a})] \) (Condition C4) is verified, and if \(a_{1}^{*}\) is superior to \(a_{2}^{*}\) (Condition C3). This condition implies the relation \((1+\lambda )\delta \dfrac{C^{\prime }(a_{2})}{C^{\prime }(a_{1})}<1\) if \(a_{1}^{*}\) is superior to \(a_{2}^{*}\), because increasing marginal abatement costs lead to \(\frac{[ C(a_{1}^{*})-C( \overset{-}{a})] }{a_{1}^{*}-\overline{a}}<C^{\prime }(a_{1}^{*})\) and \(\frac{[ C(\overset{-}{a})-C(a_{2}^{*})] }{\overline{ a}-a_{2}^{*}}>C^{\prime }(a_{2}^{*})\).

We use the first-order conditions of the programs associated with the UT and D agreements. We obtain:

$$\begin{aligned}&\text {(UT) }\gamma (1+\lambda )(NB_{2}^{U}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}} )=(1-\gamma )(NB_{1}^{U}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}}) \end{aligned}$$
(24)
$$\begin{aligned}&\text {(D) }\gamma C^{\prime }(a_{1}^{*})(NB_{2}^{D}-\overset{\wedge }{ NB_{2}})=(1-\gamma )\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2}^{*})(NB_{1}^{D}-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{1}}) \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Proposition 2 implies that \(\overline{V}^{*}\) is greater than \(V^{*}\) under Conditions C3 and C4. So we have \( \overline{V}^{*}=(\frac{\gamma (1+\lambda )}{(1-\gamma )})^{\gamma }(NB_{2}^{U}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}})> (\frac{\gamma C^{\prime }(a_{1}^{*})}{(1-\gamma )\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2}^{*})})^{\gamma }(NB_{2}^{D}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}})=V^{*}\). As \((1+\lambda )\delta \dfrac{C^{\prime }(a_{2}^{*})}{C^{\prime }(a_{1}^{*})}<1, NB_{2}^{U}\) is greater than \(NB_{2}^{D}\). Moreover \((NB_{1}^{U}-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{1}})>(NB_{1}^{D}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{1}})\) if and only if \(\dfrac{\gamma (1+\lambda )}{(1-\gamma )}(NB_{2}^{U}-\overset{ \wedge }{NB_{2}})>\dfrac{\gamma C^{\prime }(a_{1}^{*})}{(1-\gamma )\delta C^{\prime }(a_{2}^{*})}(NB_{2}^{D}-\overset{\wedge }{NB_{2}})\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bayramoglu, B., Jacques, JF. International Environmental Agreements: The Case of Costly Monetary Transfers. Environ Resource Econ 62, 745–767 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-014-9837-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-014-9837-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation