Skip to main content
Log in

On Categorial Membership

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We investigate the family of concepts that an agent comes to know through a set of defining features, and examine the role played by these features in the process of categorization. In a qualitative framework, categorial membership is evaluated through an order relation among the objects at hand, which translates the fact that an object may fall more than another under a given concept. For concepts defined by their features, this global membership order depends on the degree with which each feature applies to the objects of the universe. The passage from these individual membership degrees to a global membership order poses a problem analogous to vote aggregation in social choice theory. This similarity leads to an original solution that is particularly well-adapted to the framework of cognitive psychology. The resulting membership order extends to compound concepts, and provides a good description of the guppy paradox and the conjunction effect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We will show later that the extension of a concept exactly corresponds to the set of all objects that fall under this concept.

  2. We recall that the proof of the observations is given in the "Appendix".

  3. The original proof of this observation is due to Daniel Lehmann (2010).

References

  • Aerts, D. (2009). Quantum structure in cognition. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53-5, 314–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1953). Social choice and individual values. Cowles foundation m onographs. New York: Wiley 1964.

  • Borda, J.-Ch. (1781). Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin. Paris: Mémoires de l’Académie des Sciences.

  • Condorcet, J. A. M., De Caritat, M. (1785). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Paris: Imprimerie Royale.

  • Dubois, D., Esteva, F., Godo, L., & Prade, H. (2005). An information-based discussion of vagueness. In H. Cohen, & C. Lefebvre (Eds.), Handbook of categorization in cognitive science, (pp. 892–913).

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford:Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franco, R. (2009). The conjunction fallacy and interference effects. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53-5, 415–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a/S: Louis Nebert.

  • Freund, M. (2008). On the notion of concept I. Artificial Intelligence, 172, 570–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freund, M. (2009). On the notion of concept II. Artificial Intelligence, 173, 167–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. (1988). Overextension of conjunctive effects: Evidence for a unitary model of concept typicality and class inclusion. Journal for Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 14, 12–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. (1993). Prototype models of concept representation. In Van Mechelen I et al. (Eds.), Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive data analysis.

  • Hampton, J. (1995). Testing the prototype theory of concepts. Journal of Memory and Laguage, 34, 686–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1993). Patterns in the mind: Language and human nature. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

  • Kamp, H., & Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57, 129–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koselak, A. (2003). La semantique naturelle d’Anna Wierzbicka et les enjeux interculturels. Questions de communication, 4, 83–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, J. (2003). Ordinal decomposability and fuzzy connectives. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 136, 237–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, D. (2010). personal communication.

  • Nardi, D., & Brachman, R. (2003). An introduction to description logics. In F. Baader (Ed.), The description logic handbook (pp. 1–44). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osherson, D., & Smith, E. (1981). On the adequacy of prototype theory as a theory of concepts. Cognition, 11, 237–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osherson, D., & Smith, E. (1982). Gradedness and conceptual combination. Cognition, 12, 299–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peeters, B., & Goddard, C. (2006). The natural semantic metalanguage (nsm) approach: An overview with reference to the most important Romance languages. In B. Peeters (Ed.), Semantic primes and universal grammar (Vol. 19, pp. 13–88). Empirical Evidence from the Romance languages.

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In mind, language and reality (pp. 115–120). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. (1975). Cognitive representations of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 104, 192–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. (1975). Family resemblances: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E., & Medin, D. (1981). Categories and concepts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E., Shoben, E., & Rips, L. (1974). Structure and process in semantic memory: A featural model for semantic decisions. Psychological Review, 81, 214–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Storms, G., De Boeck, P., Hampton, J.A., Van Mechelen (1999). Predicting conjunction typicalities by component typicalities. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 6(4), 677–684.

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extension versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgement. Psychological Review, 90, 141–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (1996). Semantics: Primes and universals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. (1965). Fuzzy sets. Information and control, 8, 338–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. (1982). A note on prototype theory and fuzzy sets. Cognition, 12, 291–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Daniel Lehmann for several advices and corrections that helped improving this work. I am also indebted to the anonymous referees for their numerous and helpful remarks and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Freund.

Appendix

Appendix

Observation 1

Let \(\preceq_{\alpha}\) be the relation defined by

$$ \begin{aligned} &x\preceq_{\alpha}y\;iff\;for\;each\;feature\;f\in \Updelta(\alpha)\;such\;thaty\prec_{f}x, there\;exists\;a\;feature \\ &\quad g\in\Updelta(\alpha), g\;more salient\;than\;f, such\;that\;x\prec_{g}y. \end{aligned} $$

Then \(\preceq_{\alpha}\) is transitive.

Proof

Let xy and z be three items such that \(x \preceq_{\alpha} y\) and \(y \preceq_{\alpha} z\), and suppose that there exists \(f \in \Updelta(\alpha)\) such that such that \(z\prec_{f}x\). We have to show that there exists a feature \(g \in \Updelta(\alpha), g\) more salient than f, such that \(x\prec_{g}z\). We make a proof by cases:

  • Suppose first that \(x\preceq_{f}y\). Then we have \(z\prec_{f} y\), and there exists a feature \(k \in \Updelta(\alpha), k\) more salient than f, such that \(y\prec_{k}z\). We can suppose that k is maximally salient in \(\Updelta(\alpha)\) for this property (recall that \(\Updelta(\alpha)\) is finite). If \(x \preceq_{k}y\), we get \(x \prec_{k}z\) and we are done. Otherwise, because of the connectedness of \(\preceq_{k}\), we have \(y \prec_{k}x\). Since we supposed \(x \preceq_{\alpha} y\), this implies that there exists a concept \(g \in \Updelta(\alpha), g\) more salient than k, such that \(x \prec_{g}y\). We cannot have \(z\prec_{g}y\) otherwise there would exist \(h \in \Updelta(\alpha), h\) more salient than g, such that \(y\prec_{h}z\), contradicting the choice of k. We have therefore \(y\preceq_{g}z\), hence \(x\prec_{g}z\) as desired.

  • Suppose now that \(y\prec_{f}x\). Then there exists \(k \in \Updelta(\alpha), k\) more salient than f such that \(x\prec_{k}y\), and we can again suppose k maximally salient for this property. If \(y\preceq_{k}z\), we get \(x\prec_{k}z\) and we are through. Otherwise, we have \(z\prec_{k}y\) and there exists g more salient than k such that \(y\prec_{g}z\). Let us show that \(x\preceq_{g}y\): if this were not the case, we would have \(y\prec_{g}x\), so that there would exist h more salient than g such that \(x\prec_{h}y\). But then h would be more salient than k, which is impossible. We have therefore \(x\preceq_{g}y\), hence \(x\prec_{g}z\), and the proof is complete.

\(\square\)

Observation 2

One has xα y if and only if x f y for all features f of \(\Updelta(\alpha)\).

Proof

It is clear that xα y holds whenever x f y for all features f of \(\Updelta(\alpha)\). Suppose conversely that we do not have x f y for some feature f of \(\Updelta(\alpha)\), and let f be of maximal salience in \(\Updelta(\alpha)\) for this property. Since \(\preceq_{f}\) is a total preorder, we necessarily have \(x\prec_{f}y\) or \(y\prec_{f}x\). In the first case, and by the choice of f, we cannot have \(y \preceq_{\alpha} x\); in the second case, we cannot have \(x \preceq_{\alpha} y\). This shows that we cannot have xα y. \(\square\)

Observation 3

Define the extension Ext α of α as the set of all objects z such that \(\delta_{f}(z) = 1\quad \forall f\in\Updelta(\alpha)\). Then it holds \(x \prec_{\alpha} z\) and \(x\prec_{\alpha}^{*}z\) for all \(x \notin Ext\,\alpha\) and \(z\in Ext\,\alpha\).

Proof

If z is such that δ f (z) = 1 for all \(f\in\Updelta(\alpha)\), it follows from the definitions of \(\preceq_{\alpha}\) and \(\preceq_{\alpha}^{*}\) that one has necessarily \(x \preceq_{\alpha} z\) and \(x \preceq_{\alpha}^{*} z\) for all objects x of the universe. If moreover there exists a defining feature f such that δ f (x) < 1, these inequalities are strict, so that \(x \prec_{\alpha} z\) and \(x \prec_{\alpha}^{*}z\) as desired. \(\square\)

Observation 4

\(\preceq_{\alpha}\) and \(\preceq_{\alpha}^{*}\) are finite membership orders.

Proof

Concerning \(\preceq_{\alpha}\), the proof follows from Observation 2. As for \(\preceq_{\alpha}^{*}\), we see, again by Observation 2 that every \(\preceq_{\alpha}\)—equivalence class is embedded in a \(\preceq_{\alpha}^{*}\)-equivalence class, whence the result. \(\square\)

Observation 5

Define the extension \(Ext (\beta\,\star\,\alpha)\) of \(\beta\,\star\,\alpha\) to be the set of all \(\preceq_{\beta \star \alpha}\) -maximal elements, and let z be an arbitrary object. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  • \(z \in Ext (\beta\,\star\,\alpha)\)

  • z is \(\prec_{\beta\, \star\, \alpha}^{*}{\text{-}}maximal\)

  • \(z\in Ext\, \alpha\cap Ext\, \beta\)

  • \(x \prec_{\beta\, \star\, \alpha} z \forall x \notin Ext (\beta\, \star\, \alpha)\)

  • \(x\prec_{\beta\, \star\, \alpha}^{*} z \forall x \notin Ext (\beta\, \star\, \alpha)\).

Proof

Since we have \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}^{*} \subseteq \prec_{\beta\star\alpha}\), any \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}\)-maximal element is \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}^{*}\)-maximal. If x is not \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}^{*}\)-maximal, it holds \(x\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}^{*}z\) for any element z of Ext α ∩ Ext β, since \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}^{*}\) corresponds to the proportional order induced by the fictitious defining features set {α, β}. This shows that any \(\prec_{\beta\star \alpha}^{*}\)-maximal element must lie in Ext α ∩ Ext β, and is therefore also \(\prec_{\beta\star\alpha}\)-maximal. The proof of the Observation follows. \(\square\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Freund, M. On Categorial Membership. Erkenn 79, 1045–1068 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9584-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9584-7

Keywords

Navigation