Skip to main content
Log in

What Should we Believe About Free Will?

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Given the available evidence, I argue that we face considerable uncertainty about free will. In particular, I argue that the available philosophical evidence does not support being highly confident in our theories about the nature of free will, though this does not necessarily mean that we should suspend judgment about either incompatibilism or compatibilism. For those who accept incompatibilism, however, I argue that there is enough uncertainty about libertarian free will that they should suspend judgment about whether we are ever free, if not reject free will entirely. While I do not claim that compatibilists should be similarly agnostic about the existence of free will, I argue that most compatibilist theories are subject to considerable uncertainty as well, so that most compatibilists should be agnostic about how often we act freely. I conclude with a brief discussion of how we might address these issues going forward.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While Mele (1995), Byrd (2010), and Kearns (2015) defend positions labeled as agnostic, these agnostic views differ substantially from the position defended here. Mele is only agnostic about compatibilism. Byrd (2010) argues that we do not know whether we are morally responsible for our behavior. Kearns argues that we do not know that we are free, but he contends, nevertheless, that it is very plausible that we are (246).

  2. In making this case, I assume that it is possible to suspend belief in free will, contrary to Strawson (1962). The fact that over 16% of philosophers claim to not believe in free will lends some plausibility to this assumption. For responses to P.F. Strawson, see Russell (1992) and Strawson (1986): Chapter 5.

  3. See, for instance, van Inwagen (2010), in which he acknowledges that, despite his disagreement with David Lewis over compatibilism, there is no evidence supporting the belief that, by comparison, Lewis was lacking in his understanding of the relevant issues or in philosophical ability. Some of the participants in the philosophical debates over free will may not share a similar humility regarding their opponents, but such an attitude does not appear to be common. While I assume that such modesty is appropriate, it is worth noting that if I am wrong on this point, the concerns about the quality of the available philosophical evidence discussed below may nevertheless warrant considerable theory-uncertainty.

  4. Peers are often defined as having access to the same evidence, but as Goldman (2010: 210–212) points out, it may be difficult, if not impossible, for two disputants to have the same familiarity with all the relevant information. While I do not require that peers have access to the same evidence, I do not think that the weaker standard for epistemic peerhood employed here will be of consequence to my overall argument. For more on relaxing the evidential requirements for peerhood, see Christensen (2007: 211–212).

  5. To determine whether two philosophers are roughly equally capable, we cannot simply examine their previous judgments to see how reliable they have been. Following Elga (2007: 492–494) and Grundmann (2013), we might worry that this would imply that neither party to a philosophical dispute should see the other as an epistemic peer. See, however, Fumerton (2010), Kornblith (2010: 47–51) and Simpson (2013: 572–576) for compelling replies.

  6. The distinction between conciliatory versus steadfast approaches is common in the literature on disagreement, but it is drawn in different ways. I will count a view as being more or less conciliatory to the degree that it encourages us to lower our confidence in the face of disagreement with epistemic peers.

  7. Admittedly, this is only a very rough sketch of how we should respond to peer disagreement, but it should be sufficient for our purposes. For more detailed discussions of similar approaches, see Kelly (2010, 2013), Lackey (2010), and Thune (2010). To be clear, acknowledging a reason to think that my original judgment might have been mistaken does not mean that I should not have made it. On this point, see Lackey (2010: 316–317).

  8. See, for example, Christensen (2007) and Elga (2007).

  9. It is worth noting that while some philosophers express certainty on some issues, such as van Inwagen does on the existence of free will, others may assert and defend views without being confident they are right, perhaps in reaction to persistent peer disagreement. Reflecting on the appropriate reaction to such disagreement, for example, Fumerton (2010: 106) claims that it might be appropriate to assert and defend a philosophical position without even believing it.

  10. Cappelen (2012) denies that there is a broad reliance on intuitions in philosophy. See, however, Chalmers (2014) and Bengson (2014). To be clear, I am not suggesting that philosophers rely solely or primarily on intuition. For a discussion of some of the ways in which philosophers use intuitions, see Bengson (2014: 571–574). There is, as one might expect, considerable controversy about the nature of intuitions. See, for example, Chudnoff (2013: 1–13). If our intuitions are supposed to provide some support for our philosophical theories, then I assume such support does not imply some particularly controversial claim about their nature. If I am wrong about this, then it may turn out that there is an additional reason to be suspicious of appeals to philosophical intuitions.

  11. It is typically assumed in these discussions that we are only directly responsible for our actions when we act freely.

  12. See Frankfurt (1969).

  13. See Mele (2006: 184–195) and Pereboom (2001: 110–117), respectively.

  14. See van Inwagen (1983: 93–105, 182–188), respectively.

  15. Sommers (2015) argues that the majority of the studies of free will and moral responsibility discussed in the experimental philosophy literature are poorly designed and that the significance of the results is often overstated. I do not take up this issue here, as my goal is merely to illustrate that the available empirical evidence does not support a high level of confidence in intuitions about free will.

  16. See Shanteau (1992: 258).

  17. Feltz and Cokely (2012) argues that this and other similar studies show that experts on free will should not be highly confident in their philosophical views without further empirical investigation into possible sources of bias in their intuitions.

  18. See, for example, Schwitzgebel and Cushman (2012) and Tobia et al. (2013a, b).

  19. Weinberg et al. (2012) showed similar results concerning how ordinary epistemic intuitions are affected by the order in which thought experiments are presented.

  20. See, for example, Grundmann (2010) and Williamson (2011). Both also claim that philosophers are entitled to be confident in the reliability of their intuitions unless there is empirical evidence suggesting otherwise. If so, then I would suggest that the evidence is sufficient at this point to undermine such initial confidence when it comes to our intuitions about free will.

  21. Alexander and Weinberg (2014) makes a similar point concerning epistemic intuitions. Rini (2015) argues that it is still an open empirical question whether expert philosophers make much better use of their intuitions. If it is, then I assume that expert philosophers on free will should not be confident that they are doing so when the available evidence suggests otherwise. It is also worth noting that, given persistent peer disagreements, the appeal to expert intuition has led a large number of philosophers to false views.

  22. For a helpful discussion of studies on this issue, see section 5.2 of Buckwalter (2016). Dunaway et al. (2013) argues instead that philosophers are often good at predicting folk intuitions, but also acknowledges that there is a need for empirical verification of philosophers’ armchair assessments of what the folk are likely to say, as the reliability of these assessments is an open empirical question.

  23. Nahmias and Thompson (2014), for instance, argues that additional studies have not supported Knobe’s suggestion. It is worth noting that some philosophers would be untroubled by the suggestion that our decisions are uncaused by prior events. See, for instance, Steward (2012).

  24. I am assuming that belief in free will cannot be justified a priori. For a discussion and defense of this assumption, see De Caro (2007).

  25. Sehon (2013) examines two particular accounts of free will, the event-causal libertarianism developed by Robert Kane and the compatibilist approach defended by John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza, and concludes that we do not know enough about deliberation to confirm that either approach accurately describes deliberation. While I am sympathetic with this conclusion, I am unconvinced by his critique of Fischer’s and Ravizza’s account, as I suspect that it relies on a reading of their talk of “mechanism” that Fischer might reject (2012: 186–187). Additionally, though Sehon thinks that similar concerns likely apply to a number of alternative accounts, he does not endorse agnosticism about the existence or extent of free will.

  26. I take it that if our choices are not determined, then some neural events will not be determined. I also assume that we must turn to science to establish whether there is such neural indeterminacy. We may feel free, but this does not provide compelling evidence of neural indeterminacy. While I will not attempt to defend either assumption here, any attempt to appeal to the phenomenology of deliberation to settle matters that are treated as open scientific questions would appear to require extreme confidence about what the phenomenological data suggest and the reliability of such introspection. Positions on either of these issues are quite controversial. For example, Mele (2014: 78–81) rejects the claim that the phenomenology of deliberation suggests that there is indeterminacy in our deliberation. Likewise, the reliability of introspection is a matter of dispute. See, for example, Schwitzgebel (2008) and Pereboom (2011). Thus, I expect that this combination of views should give rise to enough theory-uncertainty to leave its defenders too hesitant to make confident pronouncements about issues that are considered open questions in science.

  27. There is still considerable disagreement among physicists about how to interpret quantum mechanics, as evidenced by a poll of participants at a conference on the foundations of quantum mechanics. See Schlosshauer et al. (2013).

  28. See Walter (2001), Balaguer (2010), and Roskies (2014).

  29. See Russell (1997: 547–548). It is worth noting that Russell focuses on claims that cannot be disproven, such as the claim that there is a teapot somewhere between Earth and Mars that is too small to be observed by us.

  30. See, for example, Balaguer (2010: 141–169), Mele (2014: 78–82), as well as Shariff et al. (2008: 192).

  31. Nahmias (2007) provides a summary of the results from social psychology. There are additional studies, however, that appear to indicate that we are sometimes able to exercise significant conscious control over our behavior, as Mele (2009: 131–144, 2014: 45–46) point out. Thus, while many psychologists appear to believe that we are rarely aware of the causes of our behavior, I agree with Nahmias (2014: 19) that the science seems far from settled at this point. For a helpful discussion of the psychological debate on this issue, see Kihlstrom (2008). Here, I will grant that we are at least sometimes aware of why we do what we do, for instance when we exert conscious control over our decisions, and I will only argue that it is uncertain just how often we have such insight.

  32. Greene (2008) argues instead that the experimental evidence suggests that, while deontological judgments are driven by rapid emotional responses, consequentialist judgments are based on more rational deliberation. See Bortolotti (2015: 95–97) for additional concerns about the model.

  33. See, for example, Saul (2013).

  34. For example, Fischer and Ravizza (1998) offers a prominent compatibilist account of moral responsibility according to which agents can only be morally responsible for their actions if they take responsibility for them. To do so, agents must recognize that it is appropriate for others to blame them for their behavior (211), where this recognition is “based, in the appropriate way, on the evidence” (213). When we are unaware of the causes of our behavior, it is difficult to see how we could recognize, based on the evidence in the appropriate way, that it is appropriate for others to blame us.

  35. Churchland and Suhler (2014a) argues that we have significant nonconscious control over our actions, while resisting using the term “free will.” Nevertheless, while arguing that conscious deliberation is not necessary for moral responsibility, Churchland and Suhler (2014b: 346) concedes that this is not the traditional view. Likewise, Arpaly (2003) argues that we can be morally responsible for our actions even when we are unaware of their causes, so long as these actions reveal important features of our moral psychology. Arpaly concludes that moral responsibility does not require agent-autonomy, which she describes as “a type of self-control” consisting of “the agent’s ability to decide which of [her motivational states] to follow” (118). Sher (2006) also suggests that we can be morally responsible for our behavior even when we are unaware of what is causing it. Sher claims that, in such situations, our behavior would not be under our voluntary control. See, also, Smith (2008), which defends a similar approach according to which moral responsibility does not require voluntary control. While Arpaly, Sher, and Smith are not addressing the requirements for free will, those who view free will as a necessary condition for moral responsibility might nevertheless appeal to a similar account of moral responsibility to argue that we can act freely even when we are unaware of why we are doing so. It is worth noting, though, that Arpaly concedes that many cases of moral responsibility are difficult to decide given our limited knowledge of the relevant psychological and neurological facts (153–159).

  36. For instance, even if we set aside the requirement that morally responsible agents take responsibility for their behavior, Fischer and Ravizza (1998: 69–82) also argues that we can only be responsible for our behavior when it is produced by a mechanism that would both exhibit an appropriate pattern of recognizing reasons to act, including moral reasons, in some suitable range of possible scenarios and lead us at least sometimes to act on those reasons. Even if such a mechanism can operate without our awareness, it is still an open question how often our behavior is produced in this way. For example, if some of our behavior stems from our automatic emotional reactions, as Haidt suggests, or from our implicit biases, we should not assume that these processes involve such a mechanism without further empirical study.

  37. Levy (2014) argues that we are not morally responsible for our decisions when we are unaware of their causes. Likewise, Smith (2015) suggests that we are often blameless for such decisions since they do not reveal the relevant features of our moral psychology. If so, then similar considerations might suggest that such decisions are not free. I believe it is best to treat this as an open question, though, until we have a better understanding of the role of consciousness in deliberation and the processes at work when we are unaware of the causes that bring about our decisions.

  38. Weinberg et al. (2010) suggests that philosophical expertise may continue to prove unreliable because, compared with experts in other disciplines whose intuitions appear more trustworthy, philosophers often cannot appeal to any clear indicators of mistaken belief and they rely much more heavily on intuitions as the main source of data. See, though, Buckwalter (2016), which argues that expert intuition in philosophy may suffer from many of the same sources of error as expert intuitions in other disciplines and that a better understanding of why expertise sometimes fails us might offer philosophers a way to avoid these mistakes.

References

  • Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. M. (2014). The ‘unreliability’ of epistemic intuitions. In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (2010). Free will as an open scientific problem. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2014). How philosopher’s use intuition and ‘intuition’. Philosophical Studies, 171, 555–576.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2015). Irrationality. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170, 465–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. (2016). Intuition fail: Philosophical activity and the limits of expertise. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92, 378–410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrd, J. (2010). Agnosticism about moral responsibility. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 40, 411–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy without intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2014). Intuitions in philosophy: A minimal defense. Philosophical Studies, 171, 535–544.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. The Philosophical Review, 116, 187–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. (2013). Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Suhler, C. L. (2014a). Agency and control: The subcortical role in good decisions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 4)., Free will and moral responsibility Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Suhler, C. L. (2014b). Responses. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 4)., Free will and moral responsibility Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro, M. (2007). The roles of conceptual analysis and empirical science. In M. Marraffa, M. De Caro, & F. Ferretti (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind: Philosophy and psychology in intersection. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunaway, B., Edmonds, A., & Manley, D. (2013). The folk probably do think what you think they think. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 421–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2007). Reflection and disagreement. Noûs, 41, 478–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2012). The philosophical personality argument. Philosophical Studies, 161, 227–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2012). Deep control: Essays on free will and value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2010). You can’t trust a philosopher. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2010). Epistemic relativism and reasonable disagreement. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonnerman, C., Reuter, S., & Weinberg, J. M. (2011). More oversensitive intuitions: Print fonts and could choose otherwise. Central Division, Minneapolis, MN: Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Philosophical Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 3)., The neuroscience of morality Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, T. (2010). Some hope for intuitions: A reply to Weinberg. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 481–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, T. (2013). Doubts about philosophy? The alleged challenge from disagreement. In T. Henning & D. Schweikard (Eds.), Knowledge, virtue, and action: Essays on putting epistemic virtues to work. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hernández-Julián, R., & Peters, C. (2017). Student appearance and academic performance. Journal of Human Capital, 11, 247–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (2002). Some neglected pathways in the free will Labyrinth. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearns, S. (2015). Free will agnosticism. Noûs, 49, 235–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2010). Peer disagreement and higher-order evidence. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2013). Disagreement and the burdens of judgment. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom, J. F. (2008). The automaticity juggernaut—or, are we automatons after all? In J. Baer, J. C. Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free? Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2014). Free will and the scientific vision. In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2010). Belief in the face of controversy. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2010). A justificationist view of disagreement’s epistemic significance. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Social epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2014). Consciousness & moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents: From self-control to autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2009). Effective intentions: The power of conscious will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2014). Free: Why science hasn’t disproved free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E. (2007). Autonomous agency and social psychology. In M. Marraffa, M. De Caro, & F. Ferretti (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind: Philosophy and psychology in intersection. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E. (2014). Is free will an illusion? Confronting challenges from the modern mind sciences. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 4)., Freedom and responsibility Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., & Thompson, M. (2014). A naturalistic vision of free will. In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2012). The indeterminist intuition: Source and status. The Monist, 95, 290–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2011). Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. A. (2015). How not to test for philosophical expertise. Synthese, 192, 431–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, A. L. (2014). Can neuroscience resolve issues about free will? In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 4)., Freedom and responsibility Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, P. (1992). Strawson’s way of naturalizing responsibility. Ethics, 102, 287–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1997). Is there a God? In J. G. Slater (Ed.), The collected papers of Bertrand Russell (Vol. 11)., Last philosophical testament, 1943–68 New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2013). Implicit bias, stereotype threat and women in philosophy. In K. Hutchison & F. Jenkins (Eds.), Women in philosophy: What needs to change?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M., Kofler, J., & Zeilinger, A. (2013). A snapshot of foundational attitudes towards quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 222–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, E., Cokely, E. T., & Feltz, A. (2011). Persistent bias in expert judgments about free will and moral responsibility: A test of the expertise defense. Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 1722–1731.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in Moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language, 27, 135–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2015). Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise, and reflection. Cognition, 141, 127–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwiztgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117, 245–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sehon, S. (2013). Epistemic issues in the free will debate: Can we know that we are free? Philosophical Studies, 166, 363–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanteau, J. (1992). Competence in experts: The role of task characteristics. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 53, 252–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shariff, A. F., Schooler, J., & Vohs, K. D. (2008). The hazards of claiming to have solved the hard problem of free will. In J. Baer, J. C. Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free? Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2006). Out of control. Ethics, 116, 285–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, R. M. (2013). Epistemic peerhood and the epistemology of disagreement. Philosophical Studies, 164, 561–577.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (2008). Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies, 138, 367–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. M. (2015). Dual-process theory and moral responsibility. In R. Clarke, M. McKenna, & A. M. Smith (Eds.), The nature of moral responsibility: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, T. (2015). Free will and experimental philosophy: An intervention. In J. Clausen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steward, H. (2012). A metaphysics of freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thune, M. (2010). ‘Partial defeaters’ and the epistemology of disagreement. The Philosophical Quarterly, 60, 355–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2013a). Moral intuitions: Are philosophers experts? Philosophical Psychology, 26, 629–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K., Chapman, G., & Stich, S. (2013b). Cleanliness is next to morality, even for philosophers. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, 195–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2010). We’re right. They’re wrong. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, H. (2001). Neurophilosophy of free will: From libertarian illusions to a concept of natural autonomy (C. Klohr, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Weinberg, J. M., Alexander, J., Gonnerman, C., & Reuter, S. (2012). Restrictionism and reflection: Challenge deflected, or simply redirected? The Monist, 95, 200–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology, 23, 331–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2011). Philosophical expertise and the burden of proof. Metaphilosophy, 42, 215–229.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeremy Byrd.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Byrd, J. What Should we Believe About Free Will?. Erkenn 86, 505–522 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00116-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00116-3

Navigation