Skip to main content
Log in

Habitual Virtuous Actions and Automaticity

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Dual process theorists in psychology maintain that the mind’s workings can be explained in terms of conscious or controlled processes and automatic processes. Automatic processes are largely nonconscious, that is, triggered by environmental stimuli without the agent’s conscious awareness or deliberation. Automaticity researchers contend that even higher level habitual social behaviors can be nonconsciously primed. This article brings work on automaticity to bear on our understanding of habitual virtuous actions. After examining a recent intuitive account of habitual actions and habitual virtuous actions, the author offers her own explanation in terms of goal-dependent automaticity. This form of automaticity provides an account of habitual virtuous actions that explains the sense in which these actions are rational, that is, done for reasons. Habitual virtuous actions are rational in the sense of being purposive or goal-directed and are essentially linked with the agent’s psychological states. Unlike deliberative virtuous actions, the agent’s reasons for habitual virtuous actions are not present to her conscious awareness at the time of acting.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Strictly speaking, the representation of the goal, and not the goal itself, is nonconsciously activated. I try to be as precise as possible, and refer mainly to the activated representation of the goal. Sometimes this locution is cumbersome, and I refer simply to the activation of the goal. One might think that referring to the representation of a goal, as opposed to simply referring to a goal, is to introduce a distinction without a difference, since having a goal is the same thing as having a representation of it. This is not quite right, however, for my representation can extend beyond the conceptual content of the goal itself. We can see this by noting that representations of goals can change, yet the goal itself remains the same. My goal to lose weight, for example, can remain essentially the same in terms of conceptual content, yet my representation of it can change from negative to positive, depending on changes in the attitude with which I view it.

  2. For consequentially ascribable versus independently intelligible desires, on which I draw for insight about goal ascription, see Dancy (1993, pp. 8–9).

  3. I am grateful to Timothy Crockett for this example.

  4. See, for example, Aristotle (1985), Foot (2001), Hursthouse (1999), McDowell (1995), Slote (2001), Swanton (2003), and Zagzebski (1996). Some consequentialist virtue theories, such as Driver (2001), are exceptions.

  5. The analogy of virtue-relevant goals with deep language structures can be taken only so far. My claim is not that representations of virtue-relevant goals are innate, as are language capacities, only that they are deep-seated.

References

  • Aarts H, Dijksterhuis A (2000) Habits as knowledge structures: Automaticity in goal–directed behavior. J Pers Soc Psychol 78:53–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1985) In: Irwin T (Transl.) Nicomachean ethics. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin MW (ed) (2005) Interpersonal cognition. Guilford, New York

  • Bargh JA (1989) Conditional automaticity: Varieties of automatic influence in social perception and cognition. In: Uleman J, Bargh J (eds) Unintended thought. Guilford, New York, pp 3–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, JA (1990) Auto-motives: Preconscious determinants of social interaction. In: Higgins E, Sorrentino R (eds) Handbook of motivation and cognition, vol 2. Guilford, New York, pp 93–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Barndollar K (1996) Automaticity in action: The unconscious as repository of chronic goals and motives. In: Gollwitzer P, Bargh J (eds) The psychology of action. Guilford, New York, pp 457–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Ferguson M (2000) Beyond behaviorism: On the automaticity of higher mental processes. Psychol Bull 126:925–945

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Gollwitzer PM (1994) Environmental control of goal-directed action: Automatic and strategic contingencies between situation and behavior. In: Spaulding W (ed) Nebraska symposium on motivation, vol 41. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, pp 71–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh JA, Gollwitzer PM, Lee-Chair A, Barndollar K, Trotschel R (2001) The automated will: Nonconscious activation and pursuit of behavioral goals. J Pers Soc Psychol 81:1014–1027

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaiken S, Trope Y (1999) Dual-process theories in social psychology. Guilford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chartrand Tanya L, Bargh John A (1996) Automatic activation of impression formation and memorization goals: Nonconscious goal priming reproduces effects of explicit task instructions. J Pers Soc Psychol 71:464–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (1993) Moral reasons. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (2000) Practical reality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1980) Essays on action and events. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Devine PG, Monteith MJ (1999) Automaticity and control in stereotyping. In: Chaiken S, Trope Y (eds) Dual-process models and themes in social and cognitive psychology. Guilford, New York, pp 339–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver J (2001) Uneasy virtue. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellenberger HF (1970) The discovery of the unconscious: The history and evolution of dynamic psychiatry. Basic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishbach A, Friedman RS, Kruglanski AW (2003) Leading us not into temptation: Momentary allurements elicit overriding goal activation. J Pers Soc Psychol 84:296–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzsimons GA, Bargh JA (2003) Thinking of you: Nonconscious pursuit of interpersonal goals associated with relationship partners. J Pers Soc Psychol 84:148–164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzsimons GM, Shah J, Chartrand TL, Bargh JA (2005) Goals and labors, friends and neighbors: Self-regulation and interpersonal relationships. In: Baldwin M (ed) Interpersonal cognition. Guilford, New York, pp 103–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot P (2001) Natural goodness. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer PM, Bargh JA (eds) (1996) The psychology of action: Linking cognition and motivation to behavior. Guilford, New York

  • Gollwitzer PM, Heckhausen H, Steller B (1990) Deliberative and implemental mind-sets: Cognitive tuning toward congruous thoughts and information. J Pers Soc Psychol 59:1119–1127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higgins ET, Sorrentino RM (eds) (1990) Handbook of motivation and cognition: Foundations of social behavior. Guilford, New York

  • Hursthouse R (1999) On virtue ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse R, Lawrence G, Quinn W (eds) (1995) Virtues and reasons: Philippa Foot and moral theory. Clarendon, Oxford

  • Johnson RN (2003) Virtue and right. Ethics 113:810–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1995) Two sorts of naturalism. In: Hursthouse R, Lawrence, G, Quinn, W (eds) Virtues and reasons: Philippa Foot and moral theory. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 149–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollard B (2003) Can virtuous actions be both habitual and rational? Ethical Theory Moral Pract 6:411–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, J (2003) Automatic for the people: How representations of significant others implicitly affect goal pursuit. J Pers Soc Psychol 84:661–681

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah JY, Kruglanski AW (2003) When opportunity knocks: Bottom-up priming of goals by means and its effects on self-regulation. J Pers Soc Psychol 84:1109–1122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote M (2001) Morals from motives. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1994) The moral problem. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding WD (ed) (1994) Integrative views of motivation, cognition, and emotion. Nebraska symposium on motivation, vol 41. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

  • Stout R (1996) Things that happen because they should: A teleological approach to action. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanton C (2003) Virtue ethics: A pluralistic view. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Uleman JS, Bargh JA (eds) (1989) Unintended thought. Guilford, New York

  • Zagzebski LT (1996) Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Timothy Crockett, Michael Monahan, Theresa Tobin, and anonymous reviewers for this journal for helpful comments on earlier versions of this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nancy E. Snow.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Snow, N.E. Habitual Virtuous Actions and Automaticity. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 9, 545–561 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-006-9035-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-006-9035-5

Key words

Navigation