Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding proper names

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a fairly general consensus that names are Millian (or Russellian) genuine terms, that is, are singular terms whose sole semantic function is to introduce a referent into the propositions expressed by sentences containing the term. This answers the question as to what sort of proposition is expressed by use of sentences containing names. But there is a second serious semantic problem about proper names, that of how the referents of proper names are determined. This is the question that I will discuss in this paper. Various views consistent with Millianism have been proposed as to how the semantic referents of proper names are determined. These views can be classified into (1) description theories and (2) causal theories, but they can also be classified into (3) social practice theories, on which a name’s referent is determined by a social practice involving the referent, and (4) individualistic theories, on which the referent of the use of a name is determined by the speaker’s state of mind. Here I argue against social practice theories of the sorts proposed by Kripke and Evans and in favor of an individualistic approach to name reference. I argue that social practice is irrelevant to determining name reference and that, as a consequence, names have no meanings in natural languages. In the second part of the paper I motivate and propose a new form of individualistic theory which incorporates features of both description theories and Evans’s social practice theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abbott B. (2002) Definites and proper names: Some bad news for the description theory. Journal of Semantics 19: 203–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abbott B. (2004) Proper names and language. In: Carlson G.N., Pelletier F.J. (eds) Reference and quantification: The Partee effect. CSLI Publications, Stanford, pp 63–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Almog J. (1984) Semantical anthropology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9: 479–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach K. (1987) Thought and reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2002). Georgione was so-called because of his name. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 73–103.

  • Berger A. (2002) Terms and truth. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge T. (1973) Reference and proper names. Journal of Philosophy 70: 183–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies M. (1981) Meaning, quantification, necessity: Themes in philosophical logic. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M. (1974) Singular terms. Journal of Philosophy 71: 183–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M. (1981) Designation. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan K.S. (1970) Proper names and identifying descriptions. Synthese 21: 335–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan K.S. (1974) Speaking of nothing. The Philosophical Review 83: 3–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne P. (2005) Situations and Individuals. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Gareth (1973/1977). The causal theory of names. In S. Schwartz (Ed.), Naming, necessity and natural kinds. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Evans G. (1977) Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses (I). Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 467–536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans G. (1979) Reference and contingency. Monist 69: 161–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans G. (1982) Varieties of reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach P.T. (1967) Intentional identity. Journal of Philosophy 64: 627–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts B. (1997) Good news about the description theory of names. Journal of Semantics 14: 319–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1968/1989). Utterer’s meaning, sentence-meaning, and word-meaning. In P. Grice (Ed.), Studies in the way of words (pp. 117–137). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Heim I. (1990) E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy 13: 137–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Justice J. (2001) On sense and reflexivity. Journal of Philosophy 98: 355–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1969) Quantifying in. In: Davidson D., Hintikka J. (eds) Words and objections: Essays on the work of W.V. Quine. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 206–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1977/1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kaplan D. (1989) Afterthoughts. In: Almog J., Perry J., Wettstein H. (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 565–614

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz J. J. (1994) Names without bearers. Philoosophical Review 103: 1–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz J.J. (2001) The end of Millianism. Journal of Philosophy 98: 137–166

    Google Scholar 

  • King, J. C. (1994). Anaphora and operators. Philosophical Prspectives, 8, Logic and Language, 221–250.

  • King, J. C. (2004). Context dependent quantifiers and donkey anaphora. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 30, 97–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, J. C. (2010). Anaphora. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Spring, 2010 ed. https://doi.org/plato.stanford.edu/entries/anaphora/.

  • Kripke S. (1972) Naming and necessity. In: Davidson D., Harman G. (eds) Semantics of natural language. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 253–255

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maier E. (2009) Proper names and indexicals trigger rigid presuppositions. Journal of Semantics 26: 253–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus R.B. (1961) Modalities and intensional languages. Synthese 13: 303–322

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J. (1977) The sense and reference of a proper name. Mind 86: 159–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, M. (1976). The reference of proper names. Dissertation, Indiana University.

  • McKinsey M. (1978a) Names and intentionality. The Philosophical Review 87: 171–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1978b) Kripke’s objections to description theories of names. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8: 485–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1981) Causes and intentions: A reply. The Philosophical Review 90: 408–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1984) Causality and the paradox of names. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9: 491–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1986) Mental anaphora. Synthese 66: 159–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1987) Apriorism in the philosophy of language. Philosophical Studies 52: 1–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (1991) The internal basis of meaning. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72: 143–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, M. (1994). Individuating beliefs. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, Philosophy of Logic and Language, 303–330.

  • McKinsey M. (1999) The semantics of belief ascriptions. Nous 33: 519–557

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey M. (2009) Thought by description. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78: 83–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale S. (1990) Descriptions. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry J. (1997) Reflexivity, indexicality, and names. In: Künne W., Newen A., Anduschus M. (eds) Direct reference, indexicality, and propositional attitudes. CSLI Publications, Stanford, pp 3–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock J.L. (1980) Thinking about an object. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5: 487–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1975) The meaning of ‘meaning’. In: Gundarson K. (Ed.) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 7. The University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 131–193

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F. (1993) Direct reference. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1918/1964). The philosophy of logical atomism. In R. Marsh (Ed.), Logic and knowledge (pp. 175–282). New York: MacMillan.

  • Salmon N. (1986) Frege’s Puzzle. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon N. (2006) A theory of bondage. Philosophical Review 115: 415–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1958). Proper names. (reprinted by C. Caton, (Ed.), 1963, from Philosophy and ordinary language (pp. 154–161). Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

  • Searle, J. (1983/2001). Proper names and intentionality. In A. Martinich (Ed.), The philosophy of language (pp. 308–324). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Sinclair C. (1990) Tracing your scottish ancestors. The Stationery Office, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1987/1988). Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. In N. Salmon & S. Soames (Eds.), Propositions and attitudes (pp. 197–239). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Soames S. (1989) Review of Collected Papers by Gareth Evans. Journal of Philosophy 86: 141–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames S. (2002) Beyond rigidity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E. (1970) Propositional attitudes de dicto and de re. Journal of Philosophy 67: 883–896

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1950/1971). On referring. In J. Rosenberg & C. Travis (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

  • Strawson P.F. (1963) Individuals. Anchor Books, Garden City, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler Z. (1971) Singular terms. In: Steinberg D., Jacobovits L. (eds) Semantics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein H. (2004) The magic prism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson N.L. (1959) Substances without substrata. Review of Metaphysics 12: 521–539

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L. (1953) Philosophical investigations. MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziff P. (1960) Semantic analysis. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael McKinsey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

McKinsey, M. Understanding proper names. Linguist and Philos 33, 325–354 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-011-9080-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-011-9080-y

Keywords

Navigation