Skip to main content
Log in

Visual prominence and representationalism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A common objection to representationalism is that a representationalist view of phenomenal character cannot accommodate the effects that shifts in covert attention have on visual phenomenology: covert attention can make items more visually prominent than they would otherwise be without altering the content of visual experience. Recent empirical work on attention casts doubt on previous attempts to advance this type of objection to representationalism and it also points the way to an alternative development of the objection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We are assuming that human visual experiences have accuracy conditions (representational contents). For a recent defense of this way of thinking about the output of the human visual system, see Burge (2010).

  2. Wu is targeting the stronger, reductive claim that experiences are phenomenally similar or different in virtue of their similarity or difference in representational content—not the weaker supervenience claim.

  3. Some have challenged the results of Carrasco et al. (2004). See Schneider (2006) and Prinzmetal et al. (2008).

  4. We are assuming with Tye (2006) and Dretske (2007) that the content of visual experience is rich in the sense that it often contains more than the subject notices. For a very different view, see O’Reagan and Noë (2001).

  5. Prinzmetal et al. (2009) distinguish PRIORITIZATION and STIMULATION, but do not discuss STANDARDS. Prinzmetal and Landau (2010) argue that there is experimental data which favors STIMULATION over the serial version of PRIORITIZATION. They do not discuss the parallel version of PRIORITIZATION, and they fail to realize that the data discussed actually count against STIMULATION as much as the serial version of PRIORITIZATION. For their data and argument, see Prinzmetal and Landau (2010, pp. 52–55). According to their accumulator model (STIMULATION), the cue is taken as evidence for a target at the cued location. Otherwise, evidence accumulates at the same rate for the attended and non-attended locations, and the threshold is the same for each location. It follows that, for the two-target trials, the non-cued location should never win the race to threshold, yet the target at the non-cued location is reported 20% of the time. In order for their accumulator model to work, we need an additional stipulation: when the non-cued location wins, it does not simply “win the race to threshold.” Instead, the cued location reaches threshold first but (somehow) this event fails to produce a response; meanwhile, the non-cued location continues to accumulate evidence and reaches threshold at a later time, producing a response. With this additional stipulation, however, the experimental evidence no longer counts against the serial version of PRIORITIZATION. We could say that subjects tend to begin by assessing the evidence for the cued location. On occasion the evidence passes threshold without triggering a response. In these cases the subjects assess the evidence at the non-cued location and respond to the target there. The serial version of PRIORITIZATION is now consistent with the timing of subjects’ responses. It may seem implausible that evidence would pass threshold and yet not trigger a response. Note, though, that, if we disallow this possibility, the experimental evidence is inconsistent with STIMULATION as well as with the serial version of PRIORITIZATION. On the other hand, if we embrace this possibility, the experimental evidence is consistent with both of these models.

  6. The idea that feature-based attention does not affect the accuracy of perceptual judgments has been challenged by more recent research, as reviewed in Carrasco (2011). Our challenge to representationalism rests, however, on the results of Prinzmetal and colleagues rather than those of Moore and Egeth. Moore and Egeth (1998) is still noteworthy for two reasons. First, it provides a model for the prioritization-based account we offer for the results of Prinzmetal et al. Second, it suggests the possibility that, under certain circumstances, feature-based attention affects the phenomenology but not the content of visual experience, a possibility that warrants further investigation.

  7. For the idea that experience can have an assertoric character, see Pryor (2000) and Matthen (2005). Of course, the senses do not literally assert anything: the output of vision is like assertion insofar as it plays the role of informing/reporting.

  8. It can be difficult to identify the assertoric character of experience. A brief comment on the nature of itches may help. It is somewhat doubtful that itches merely report or inform. After all, we have a hard time understanding how itches might be accurate or inaccurate. It seems more plausible to suppose that itches command scratching here now (Hall 2008; Klein 2007; Tumulty 2009). On the face of it, what is commanded by the itch, the content of the itch, is something that can be common to a tactile perception. We can also perceive that there is scratching here now, as when the command is satisfied. Attending to the felt difference between an itch and a correlate tactual perception of scratching is useful for picking out the assertoric character of the latter: we are evidently attending to something other than truth-evaluable content, which is roughly the same for both states.

  9. This term is due to Bill Lycan, who writes: “Now, I am myself a quasi-representationalist at best…because I have no official reason to deny that part of phenomenal character, even within a single sense modality, is constituted by functional rather than representational properties” (Lycan 1996, pp. 134–135)

  10. Cf. Smithies (2011).

References

  • Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues, 20, 23–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Carrasco, M. (2011). Visual attention: The past 25 years. Vision Research, 51, 1484–1525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrasco, M., Ling, S., & Read, S. (2004). Attention alters appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 7, 308–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrasco, M., & Yeshurun, Y. (2009). Covert attention effects on spatial resolution. Progress in Brain Research, 176, 65–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2010). The character of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2007). What change blindness teaches about consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 216–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egly, R., Driver, J., & Rafal, R. D. (1994). Shifting visual attention between objects and locations: Evidence from normal and parietal lesion subjects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 123, 161–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S., & Carrasco, M. (2006). Exogenous attention and color perception: Performance and appearance of saturation and hue. Vision Research, 46, 4032–4047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, R. (2008). If it itches, scratch! Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 525–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). Principles of Psychology (Vol. 1). New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2007). An imperative theory of pain. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 517–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, C. M., & Egeth, H. (1998). How does feature-based attention affect visual processing? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 24, 1296–1310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). Attention and perceptual content. Analysis, 70, 263–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2007). Against intentionalism. Philosophical Studies, 136, 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Reagan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinzmetal, W., & Landau, A. N. (2010). Dissecting spatial visual attention. In V. Coltheart (Ed.), Tutorials in visual cognition (pp. 43–66). Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinzmetal, W., Long, V., & Leonhardt, J. (2008). Involuntary attention and brightness contrast. Perception and Psychophysics, 70, 1139–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinzmetal, W., Zvinyatskovskiy, A., Gutierrez, P., & Dilem, L. (2009). Voluntary and involuntary attention have different consequences: The effect of perceptual difficulty. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62, 352–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Nous, 34, 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, K. A. (2006). Does attention alter appearance? Perception and Psychophysics, 68, 800–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shomstein, S., & Yantis, S. (2002). Object-based attention: Sensory modulation or priority setting? Perception and Psychophysics, 64, 41–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2011). What is the role of consciousness in demonstrative thought? The Journal of Philosophy, 108, 5–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. (2010). Attention and intentionalism. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(239), 325–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tumulty, M. (2009). Pains, imperatives, and intentionalism. The Journal of Philosophy, 106, 161–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2006). Nonconceptual content, richness, and fineness of grain. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 504–530). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2011). What is conscious attention? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 93–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Special thanks to Neil Mehta and an anonymous reviewer for insightful comments. Thanks also to Benj Hellie for useful comments on an antecedent to this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Todd Ganson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ganson, T., Bronner, B. Visual prominence and representationalism. Philos Stud 164, 405–418 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9853-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9853-3

Keywords

Navigation