Skip to main content
Log in

Do evolutionary debunking arguments rest on a mistake about evolutionary explanations?

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many moral philosophers accept the Debunking Thesis, according to which facts about natural selection provide debunking explanations for certain of our moral beliefs. I argue that philosophers who accept the Debunking Thesis beg important questions in the philosophy of biology. They assume that past selection can explain why you or I hold certain of the moral beliefs we do. A position advanced by many prominent philosophers of biology implies that this assumption is false. According to the Negative View, natural selection cannot explain the traits of individuals. Hence, facts about past selection cannot provide debunking explanations for any of our moral beliefs. The aim of this paper is to explore the conflict between the Debunking Thesis and the Negative View.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Crisp (2006), de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2012), Huemer (2008), Joyce (2000, 2001, 2006), Parfit (2011), Rosenberg (2011), Ruse (1986), Singer (1981, 2005, 2006). Kahane (2011) and Street (2006, 2008, 2011) hedge this conclusion: natural selection explanations are debunking iff we assume some form of meta-ethical realism.

  2. Pust (2001, 2004), Sober (1984, 1995), Walsh (1998), Walsh et al. (2002). In some respect, this claim is also endorsed by Lewens (2001) and Matthen (1999, 2002, 2003); see Sects. 3 and 4 for further discussion.

  3. See, e.g., Joyce (2006), Kahane (2011).

  4. Joyce (2006), Ruse (1986). Cf. Gibbard (1990).

  5. Joyce (2001), Ruse (1986), Parfit (2011). Cf. Nozick (1981, 342–348).

  6. See also Huemer (2008), Rosenberg (2011). For further discussion of Street’s view, see Sect. 5.

  7. Crisp (2006), Huemer (2008), Singer (2005), Parfit (2011).

  8. Joyce (2006), Kahane (2011), Rosenberg (2011), Ruse (1986).

  9. Kahane (2011), Street (2006).

  10. Joyce (forthcoming).

  11. These positions are sometimes run together: e.g., by Martinez and Moya (2011) and Neander (1988, 1995a, b). Forber (2005) is careful to distinguish these questions, as are Razeto-Barry and Frick (2011).

  12. See Cummins (1975).

  13. See Dawkins (1986), Forber (2005), Neander (1995a).

  14. My reasoning in the following draws on a similar discussion in Sober (1995).

  15. Someone might think that since o’s existence is necessary for o to have T, explaining o’s existence partially explains why o has T, and so selection for T can explain why o has T if it can explain why o exists. But in that case, whenever natural selection explains an organism’s existence, it would explain all of its properties. Thus, in our example, selection for the trait of reciprocity would explain why I wear blue jeans or once owned a bike with a red frame. This, I take it, is absurd.

  16. See Matthen (1999), Pust (2001).

  17. Nanay (2005, 2010) provides a recent argument against the Negative View. For replies, see Helgeson (2013), Stegmann (2010a, b). Birch (2012) argues that the Negative View is ruled out if we adopt a criterion of explanatory relevance proposed by Strevens (2008: 174–177).

  18. I have modified the details of this case slightly.

  19. See McLoone (2013) for a suggested revision of the Negative View that avoids counterexamples of this kind.

  20. Ariew (1996, 1999), Samuels (2002, 2004), Sober (1998), Stich (1975).

  21. For a similar view, see Singer (1981).

  22. See Nucci (2001), Turiel (1983, 2006).

  23. This contradicts the view of the developmental psychologists responsible for the research discussed by Joyce. See, in particular, Nucci (2001: 13).

  24. See Bowles and Gintis (2011), Henrich and Henrich (2007), Richerson and Boyd (2005), Sober and Wilson (1998). More exactly, the emphasis is on gene-culture co-evolution, which involves reciprocal interactions between cultural and genetic inheritance, as in the acquisition of lactase persistence by dairying peoples in Europe and Africa.

  25. On which, see Wilson and Wilson (2007).

  26. See Maynard-Smith (1964), Williams (1966).

  27. Henrich and Boyd (1998).

  28. I omit any supporting references to help test your intuitions on this point.

  29. For further development of this line of response to Street, see Setiya (2012).

  30. Some philosophers (e.g., Bergmann 2006, Pryor 2004), believe it can be permissible to use bootstrapping reasoning to certify the reliability of a given method of belief-formation provided one has no antecedent reason to doubt the reliability of the method. So far as I am aware, no one defends the view that bootstrapping reasoning is acceptable in a case like that described here. Thus, Bergmann says: “You can't sensibly come to trust a doubted witness on the basis of that very witness's testimony on his own behalf” (180).

  31. For example, Brink (1989), Cuneo (2006), Majors (2003), Oddie (2005), Sturgeon (1985, 1986, 2006), Wedgwood (2007), Wright (1992).

  32. For an argument that familiar evolutionary debunking arguments rest on bad epistemology, see White (2010).

  33. See also Street (2006: 113–114).

  34. For recent supporting evidence, see de Waal (1996, 2006).

  35. Weinberg et al. (2001).

  36. See Mogensen (2014) for a detailed development of this kind of argument.

References

  • Ariew, A. (1996). Innateness and canalization. Philosophy of Science, 63, S19–S27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. (1999). Innateness is canalization: In defense of a developmental account of innateness. In V. G. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays (pp. 117–138). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2012). The negative view of natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C, 43, 569–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2011). A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2008). Darwinian skepticism about moral realism. Philosophical Issues, 18, 186–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (2006). Reasons and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2006). Moral facts as configuring causes. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87, 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1879/2004). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex (2nd ed.). London: Penguin.

  • Dawkins, R. (1986). The blind watchmaker. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Lazari-Radek, K., & Singer, P. (2012). The objectivity of ethics and the unity of practical reason. Ethics, 123, 9–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. B. M. (1996). Good natured: The origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. B. M. (2006). Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. (2005). On the explanatory roles of natural selection. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 329–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1994). Hooking Leviathan by its past. In his (2011) Dinosaur in a haystack: Reflections in natural history (pp. 359–376). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Helgeson, C. (2013). What selection can and cannot explain: A reply to Nanay’s critique of Sober. Philosophy of Science, 80, 155–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., & Boyd, R. (1998). The evolution of conformist transmission and the emergence of between-group differences. Evolution and Human Behavior, 19, 215–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, N., & Henrich, J. (2007). Why humans cooperate: A cultural and evolutionary explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2008). Revisionary intuitionism. Social Philosophy and Policy, 25, 368–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2000). Darwinian ethics and error. Biology and Philosophy, 15, 713–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (forthcoming). Evolution, truth-tracking, and moral skepticism. In B. Reichardt (Ed.), Problems of goodness: New essays in metaethics.

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45, 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1981). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2001). Sex and selection: A reply to Matthen. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 589–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Majors, B. (2003). Moral explanations and the special sciences. Philosophical Studies, 113, 121–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinez, M., & Moya, A. (2011). Natural selection and multi-level causation. Philosophy & Theory in Biology, 3, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (1999). Evolution, Wisconsin style: Selection and the explanation of individual traits. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 143–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2002). Origins are not essences in evolutionary systematics. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 32, 167–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2003). Is sex really necessary? And other questions for Lewens. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 297–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. (1964). Group selection and kin selection. Nature, 201, 1145–1147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLoone, B. (2013). Selection explanations of token traits. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 342–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mogensen, A. (2014). Evolutionary debunking arguments in ethics. D. Phil. thesis, University of Oxford.

  • Nanay, B. (2005). Can cumulative selection explain adaptation? Philosophy of Science, 72, 1099–1112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). Natural selection and the limitations of environmental resources. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 418–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1988). What does natural selection explain? Correction to Sober. Philosophy of Science, 55, 422–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995a). Pruning the tree of life. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995b). Explaining complex adaptations: A reply to Sober’s ‘reply to Neander’. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 583–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nucci, L. P. (2001). Education in the moral domain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2005). Value, reality, and desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1970). The structure of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 62–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2004). What’s wrong with Moore’s argument? Philosophical Issues, 14, 349–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2001). Natural selection explanation and origin essentialism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31, 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2004). Natural selection and the traits of individual organisms. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 765–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Razeto-Barry, P., & Frick, R. (2011). Probabilistic causation and the explanatory role of natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42, 344–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2011). The atheist’s guide to reality: Enjoying life without illusions. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1986). Taking Darwin seriously: A naturalistic approach to philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M., & Wilson, E. O. (1986). Moral philosophy as applied science. Philosophy, 61, 173–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind and Language, 17, 233–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2004). Innateness in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 136–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2012). Knowing right from wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1981). The expanding circle: Ethics and sociobiology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2005). Ethics and intuitions. Journal of Ethics, 9, 331–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2006). Review: Richard Joyce, The evolution of morality. Notre dame philosophical reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/25012/?id=6383. Last accessed October 24, 2013.

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1995). Natural selection and distributive explanation: A reply to Neander. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 384–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1998). Innate knowledge. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/P027. Last accessed December 13, 2011.

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. E. (2010a). What can natural selection explain? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 61–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. E. (2010b). Reply to Bence Nanay’s ‘Natuarl selection and the limited nature of environmental resources’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 420–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1975). Introduction. In S. Stich (Ed.), Innate Ideas (pp. 1–22). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Reply to Copp: Naturalism, normativity, and the varieties of realism worth worrying about. Philosophical Issues, 18, 207–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2011). Mind-independence without mystery: Why quasi-realists can’t have it both ways. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in meta-ethics (Vol. 6, pp. 1–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, N. L. (1985). Moral explanations. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 229–255). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, N. L. (1986). Harman on moral explanations of natural facts. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24(Suppl 1), 69–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, N. L. (2006). Moral explanations defended. In J. Dreier (Ed.), Contemporary debates in moral theory (pp. 241–262). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: Morality & convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. (2006). The development of morality. In W. Damon, R. M. Lerner, & N. Eisenberg (Eds.), Handbook of child psychology, 6th ed., Vol. 3: Social, emotional, and personality development (pp. 789–857). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (1998). The scope of selection: Sober and Neander on what natural selection explains. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, 250–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M., Lewens, T., & Ariew, A. (2002). The trials of life: Natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science, 69, 452–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2007). The nature of normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2010). You just believe that because…. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 573–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S., & Wilson, E. O. (2007). Rethinking the theoretical foundations of sociobiology. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 82, 327–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1992). Truth and objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper, I'm grateful to Krister Bykvist, Ellen Clarke, Daan Evers, Hilary Greaves, participants at the 2014 Philosophy of Biology in the UK conference in Cambridge and at the 2014 Experiments and Intuitions conference at Ertegun House, Oxford, as well as to students participating in my graduate seminar on evolutionary debunking arguments at Oxford in Hilary Term 2015. Last but not least, I would like to thank an anonymous referee at this journal for insightful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas L. Mogensen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mogensen, A.L. Do evolutionary debunking arguments rest on a mistake about evolutionary explanations?. Philos Stud 173, 1799–1817 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0579-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0579-x

Keywords

Navigation