Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

The essay deals with the mechanism of interpretation for legal metaphorical expressions. Firstly, it points out the perspective the cognitive approach induced about legal metaphors; then it suggests that this perspective gains in plausibility when a new bilateral model of language understanding is endorsed. A possible sketch of the meaning-making procedure for legal metaphors, compatible with this new model, is then proposed, and illustrated with some examples built on concepts belonging to the Italian Civil Code. The insights the bilateral model of understanding provides are compared with the practice followed by legal communities for dealing with the metaphorical expressions they coin and use.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. [16]. For general applications of the cognitive approach to Law, [714].

  2. Analyzing the existing literature on legal metaphors (produced by jurists, linguists, philosophers, rhetoricians, cognitive psychologists, and literary theorists), Smith [18] detected four types of metaphor operating in persuasive legal discourse: those that achieved the status of judicial principles governing an issue; metaphoric constructs playing the role of tools of analysis used to reason through legal issues; metaphors entailed by the writing style of a legal author; metaphors inherent to language itself. A transversal distinction can be traced between extra-linguistic metaphors, namely symbols metaphorically used in the practice of Law [29], conceptual metaphors underpinning legal constructs and lines of reasoning, and metaphors fully expressed in the legal languages.

  3. Metaphors play an essential role in normative texts, even though there are different opinions about their pervasiveness [4244]: their vagueness allows legal systems to balance all-inclusiveness and determinacy or precision [45].

  4. While metaphorical schemes such as “knowledge as vision” shape legal reasoning in a general way and not exclusively—which is not to say that their use has not got peculiar consequences for it [19, 20, 30]-, schemes such as social entities like rational agents characterize law more directly. Following Kuhn [31], they can be considered disciplinary matrix referring to beliefs, values, techniques, a legal community has more or less consciously decided to use in order to master a given conceptual domain.

  5. Through metaphors law keeps in touch with society because their terms come (usually) from ordinary language, and in facts the historical uses these terms in non-legal communities provide some insights into the boundaries within which any legal interpreter considers herself confined. How the legal community might co-opt and adapt certain metaphorical terms for use in the making of meaning in contemporary legal decisions has provided substantial insights into the relations between changing social and political relations and the range of uses to which a metaphor might be put.

  6. “Metaphor and metonymy can be used to reverse, modify or change meanings. This rhetorical tool may be used by anyone. But, it is most dangerous when used by an authority to linguistically validate its own ideology” [47: 216]. The choice of metaphors used in codes or Directives may also be linked (consciously or not) to political orientations. [34]. A deconstructive analysis of open normative metaphors is a tool for raising awareness of the unconscious cultural influence that may influence the judgements of legal interpreters. A necessary step of this clarification is estranging the already familiar rather than familiarising what is strange; making what is assumed as known strange again can be achieved by “decontextualizing the obvious and then recontextualizing it in a new way” [48: 4].

  7. Most of the expressions occurring in legal texts have a metaphorical origin and they all share some vagueness [35]: however, some of them are more metaphorical and more legal than others. Their prompting a creative meaning making is not obliterated as it happens for other legal expressions with a metaphorical origin (such as obligation), but it is rather exploited explicitly; furthermore, they were expressly coined to denote legal concept. Directive more then descriptive, these expressions are concrete sets of implicit rules recognised by the community as exemplars for managing new areas of the Law. For examples of legal metaphorical expressions in common Law cf., amongst others, [15, 28, 3841].

  8. Metaphors used in normative texts represent ‘junction points’ of legal systems necessary for their adaptation to possible concrete cases. When they are open to interpretation, their contact with ordinary language turns them into channels through which codes keep in touch with cultural values and beliefs shared by (part of) the society, and then can be constantly updated, changing meaning without changing words.

  9. The story of the civil fruits concept in romanistic systems shows how legal communities forge, open and close a metaphor in order to meet juridical, social, ethical and economical developments. For a reconstruction of the historical and ideological context in which the notion of civil fruits and that of interests as civil fruits grew up, cf. [49, 50]. Although with differences consequent to their dogmatic derivation, most civil codes contain the civil fruits concept (for a comparative perspective cf. [49, 50]) and define it through the same mechanism: an intensional description (in which either the terms use or enjoyment or both occur and the proviso that civil fruits accrue day by day depending on the period of entitlement, cf. for instance, I.C.C., art. 821: “I frutti civili si acquistano giorno per giorno, in ragione della durata del diritto”) plus a closed list of category of items the concept subsumes (instances slightly vary in the different codes: for instance, the art. 537 of the Civil code of the State of Louisiana defines civil fruits as “rents of real property, interest of money, annuities and all other kinds of revenue or income derived from property by the operation of the law or private agreement, or as the profits, returns or compensation a person receives from another, for the use or enjoyment of a thing”). Common law lacks a concept analogous to civil fruits, but political economy adopted the expression for representing monetary returns as belonging to some capital (property) source, and the metaphor is used in taxation law for both representing monetary returns as `fruits’ and capital sources (`trees’) as productive origins of monetary gains, since it makes questions more easily understood and followed than legal proprietary terms. For a comparative perspective between the civil law concept of ‘civil fruit’ and the English common law concept of ‘income’, cf. [36].

  10. I.C.C., art. 820: “Sono frutti civili quelli che si ritraggono dalla cosa come corrispettivo del godimento che altri ne abbia. Tali sono gli interessi dei capitali (1224, 1282, 1815), i canoni enfiteutici (957 e seg.), le rendite vitalizie (1872 e seg.) e ogni altra rendita, il corrispettivo delle locazioni (1571 e seg.)”.

  11. For the origin of this metaphor, cf. [51].

  12. I.C.C., art 1027: “La servitù prediale consiste nel peso imposto sopra un fondo per l’utilità di un altro fondo appartenente a diverso proprietario (1071, 1100)”.

  13. I.C.C., art. 1028: “L'utilità può consistere anche nella maggiore comodità o amenità del fondo dominante. Può del pari essere inerente alla destinazione industriale del fondo (1073 e seguente)”. I.C.C. divides servitudes in coercive and voluntary (art. 1031): other codes in urban and rural, cf. for instance the Civil code of the State of Louisiana, art. 643.

  14. For instance, the I.C.C. uses it without defining it (cf. artt. [31]; 23, 25, 634, 1229, 1343, 1354, 2031, 2332). As opposed to fruits and predial servitude, the metaphor public order does not come from Roman Law, but was used for the first time in Code Napoléon. For a reconstruction of its coin and use, cf. [52].

  15. As an effect of the implementation of the EU Directive on Unfair Terms in Consumer Contracts (93/13/EEC).

  16. The distinction between open and closed metaphors echoes the difference made by Cornelia Müller between sleeping and waking metaphors [56]: as opposed to other labels such as conventional/novel, dead/alive, usual/new, both distinctions underline the interpretive attitude towards metaphors rather then their linguistic characteristics. As regards to legal metaphors, the choice of the adjectives closed or open is meant to highlight the role of the communitarian decision about their status.

  17. Parallel Distributed Processing models coined by connectionism (not specifically for language understanding, but cf. [63]), suggested that processing on parallel levels could do the same work as a long serial processing and was biologically more plausible. The asset is shared by the models conceived for language understanding by Recanati.

  18. The idea seemed awkward as regards to language understanding specifically. On the contrary, the idea that more than one mind cohabits in the same individual has been explored at various times. Forty years ago, split-brain experiments [6468] prompted a renewal of the old debate about the permanence of the perception of the unity of the Self [6977] which led to theories assessing that the Subject has many local minds prevailing for specific tasks (language, visuo-spatial abilities, etc.), agencies of which conscience is only the ‘speaker’ or an imaginary character created by the brain in order to better cognitive performances and social interactions. These theories of conscience did not tackle however the possibility that language interpretation is simultaneously run by two minds (on the contrary, they talk of a linguistic mind, a visual mind, etc.).

  19. Reasons for theoretical awkwardness of this idea would deserve an entire essay. Amongst them: the Aristotelian idea of the simplicity of the linguistic intellect, that scholastics made necessary part of philosophical enquiry about language; the alleged supremacy of semantics over pragmatics theorized in first half of the last century; the analogy with language processors that characterized the reflection of the other second half. Objections moved to the possibility of the Self as a society of ideas stand against the idea as well (cf. n. [18]): as regards the perception of language understanding as performed by a unitary subject, Gazzaniga has recently proposed that it could be the outcome of a merging effect performed by the LH that effaces all contrasts that may have occurred during the different streams of analysis [68].

  20. Tests show that “qualitatively different semantic processing is manifest in distinct patterns of sensitivity to various semantic relations for words presented to the LH or RH of healthy subjects, via the right or left visual hemifield” ([80]: 512; cf. also [83]).

  21. “Evidence points to RH processing being more coarsely tuned than LH processing, because a greater spread of inputs and outputs in RH semantic areas produces more diffuse semantic activation, compared with homologous LH semantic areas. This view is consistent with data suggesting that the RH is generally more interconnected than the LH. Compared with the LH, the RH has a greater proportion of white matter […], a higher correlation of activity across regions, more diffuse electrophysiological responses, and more diffuse functional […] deficits consequent to similar sized brain lesions. This view is also consistent with asymmetries in cortical microcircuitry of language areas that influence how neurons spread information. […] Overall, these microcircuitry asymmetries suggest broader input and projection fields, and greater functional overlap across processing units in the RH than in the LH – precisely the conditions that should foster coarser coding.” ([80]: 513). Cf. also [83].

  22. After Arbib and Rizzolatti, language system evolved after the visuo-motorial one [9193].

  23. Vision is performed by the magno system, exploring everything falls in the whole visual field at low resolution, and the parvo system, working at high resolution and analyzing in detail objects populating a very small area of this space. Following the analogy between visual exploration system and language understanding system, this model of language understanding hypothesizes that contextual and semantic analysis, like peripheral and central vision, are specializations of the same primitive system of analysis. In this way, it maintains specific skills and competences of semantic and contextual analysis claimed by their respective supporters (for an overview, [94]) without excluding possible redundancies.

  24. Moderate contextualism is compatible with the Merkl-Kelsen position, although considering, as opposed to this, ambiguity as systemic ([57]: 118).

  25. Several models of language understanding, recognizing contextual analysis a role more or less relevant, share the unitary or serial stance rejected by bilateral models. The fictive ‘traditional model’ here sketched assigns contextual analysis a relevant role in order to highlight that this stance is shared not only by models keen to semantic minimalism, but also by those endorsing a moderate contextualism.

  26. This formalization of metaphor, suggested by Lakoff [2], was proposed by Nehaniv [99] and Indurkhya [100].

  27. Provisional projections of inferences from source onto target may start well before all admissible coordination rules amongst the two domains have been set up: selecting different enrichments of the basic model of source means building different coordination relationships with the target domain, and this means trying different sets of semantic projections onto it to be valued in the light of their fruitfulness.

  28. Although the mapping between the domains suggested by the text in which the open legal metaphor occurs is part of the implicit halo of meaning this very text conveys and rhetorical techniques for recovering this halo are available, they do not eliminate discretion, since they entail a choice between possible paraphrases that select a possible implicit sense at the price of discarding another possible one. Building this mapping would be a matter of choice even if the domains were isomorphic, and then their coordination given a priori. Even in this ideal case, the interpreter should have to choose which convention of coordination holds between them: specificity of their elements (the fact that, after all, they are different domains) implies that between them relationships not shared by entities to which they are connected may occur and vice versa ([101]: §13, *10).

  29. In this sense, considering the points of choice in the meaning-making of the metaphor may be of help both when the ground of the decision is produced and when it is interpreted.

References

  1. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Johnson, Mark. 1987. The body in the mind: The bodily basis of meaning, imagination, and reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Langacker, Ronald W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive grammar: Theoretical prerequisities. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Gardner, Howard E. 1985. The mind’s new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Lakoff, George. 1996. Moral politics. What conservatives know that liberals don’t. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Lakoff, George. 2004. Don’t think of an elephant: Know your values and frame the debate. New York: Chelsea Green Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Lakoff, George, and The Rockridge Institute. 2006. Thinking points: Communicating our American values and vision. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux Paperbacks.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Johnson, Mark (ed.). 1981. Philosophical perspectives on metaphor. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Johnson, Mark. 1993. Moral imagination: Implications of cognitive science for ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Winter, Steven L. 2001. A clearing in the forest: Law, Life, and Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Caterina, Raffaele (ed.). 2008. I fondamenti cognitivi del diritto. Bruno Mondadori, Percezioni, rappresentazioni, comportamenti. Milan: Bruno Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Pierre, Schlag. 1989. Missing pieces: A cognitive approach to law. Texas Law Review 68(6): 1195.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Winter, Steven L. 1988. The metaphor of standing and the problem of self-governance. Stanford Law Review 40: 1371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Winter, Steven L. 1989. Transcendental nonsense, metaphoric reasoning, and the cognitive stakes for law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 137: 1105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Smith, Michael R. 2002. Advanced legal writing: Theories and strategies in persuasive writing. New York: Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Smith, Michael R. 2007. Levels of metaphor in persuasive legal writing. Mercer Law Review 58: 919.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Berger, Linda. 2004. What is the sound of a corporation speaking? How the cognitive theory of metaphor can help lawyers shape the law. Journal of the Association of Legal Writing Directors 2: 169.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hibbitts, Bernard J. 1994. Making sense of metaphors: Visuality, aurality, and the reconfiguration of american legal discourse. Cardozo Law Review 16: 229.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Morra, Lucia, Carla Bazzanella, and Piercarlo Rossi. 2006. Metaphor in legal language: Clarity or obscurity? In Legal language and the search for clarity. Practice and Tools, eds. Anne Wagner and Sophie Cacciaguidi-Fahy. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bazzanella, Carla, Lucia Morra, and Piercarlo Rossi. 2008. L’approccio cognitivo alla metafora nel linguaggio giuridico. In I fondamenti cognitivi del diritto. Percezioni, rappresentazioni, comportamenti, ed. Raffaele Caterina. Milan: Bruno Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Sweetser, Eve E. 1990. From etymology to pragmatics. Metaphorical and cultural aspects of semantic structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Gore, Stephanie A. 2003. “A rose by any other name”: Judicial use of metaphors for new technologies. University of Illinois Journal of Law, Technology & Policy 137: 1105.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Pezzin, C. 1996. La metafora nell’argomentazione retorico-giuridica. Verona: Cierre Edizioni.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sarra, C. 2006. Metafora e diritto. In Interpretazione giuridica e retorica forense. Il problema della vaghezza del linguaggio nella ricerca della verità processuale, eds. Maurizio Manzin and Paolo Sommaggio. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Calleros, Charles R. 2002. Legal method and writing. New York: Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Bosmajian, Haig. 1992. Metaphor and reason in judicial opinions. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Costantini, Cristina. 2007. La legge e il Tempio. Storia comparata della giustizia inglese. Roma: Carocci Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Veronesi, Daniela. 2000. La metafora negli articoli scientifici giuridici: Linguaggio, testo, discorso. In Linguistica giuridica italiana e tedesca–Rechtslinguistik des Deutschen und Italienischen, ed. Daniela Veronesi. Padova: Unipress.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962, 19692. The structure of scientific revolution. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  32. Joo, Thomas W. 2001. Contract, property and the role of metaphor in corporations law. UC Davis Law Review 35: 779.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Pagallo, Ugo. 2008. Fuor di metafora: Il caso della ‘rete nel diritto’ tra fondamenti e cognizione di causa. In I fondamenti cognitivi del diritto. Percezioni, rappresentazioni, comportamenti, ed. Raffaele Caterina. Milan: Bruno Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cohen, Glenn I., and Jonathan H. Blavin. 2002. Gore, Gibson, and Goldsmith. The Evolution of Internet Metaphors in Law and Commentary. Harvard Journal of Law and Technology 16(1): 265.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Luzzati, Claudio. 2000. Le metafore della vaghezza. In Analisi e diritto 1999. Ricerche di giurisprudenza analitica, eds. Paolo Comanducci and Riccardo Guastini. Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Graziadei, Michele. 2002. Tuttifrutti. In Themes in comparative law. In honourof Bernard Rudden, eds. Peter Birks and Arianna Pretto. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Morra, Lucia, and Carla Bazzanella. 2002. Considerazioni sul “buon padre di famiglia”. Rivista critica del diritto privato XX(4): 529.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Blasi, Vincent. 2004. Holmes and the marketplace of ideas. Supreme Court Review 1: 45.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Cole, David. 1986. Agon at Agora: Creative misreadings in the first amendment tradition. Yale Law Journal 95: 857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Diana, Jennifer. 2005. Note, apples and oranges and olives? Oh my! fellers, the sixth amendment, and the fruit of the poisonous tree doctrine. Brooklyn Law Review 71: 985.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ross, Thomas. 1989. Metaphor and paradox. Georgia Law Review 23: 1055.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Bhatia, Vijay K., Jan Engberg, Maurizio Gotti, and Dorothee Heller (eds.). 2005. Vagueness in normative texts. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Bourcier, Danièle, and Pierre Mackay (eds.). 1992. Lire le Droit. Langue, texte, cognition. Paris: Librairie Générale de Droit et de Jurisprudence.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Scalia, Antonin. 1997. A matter of interpretation: Federal courts and the law. An essay. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ajani, Gianmaria. 2005. The transplant of vague notions. In Ius unum–lex multiplex. Liber Amicorum Studia Zoltán Péteri Dedicata, eds. István H. Szilágyi and Máté Szerk Paksy. Budapest: Szent István Társulat.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Monateri, Pier Giuseppe. 1984. La Sineddoche. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Facchini, Mark, and Peter A. Grossman. 1999. Metaphor and metonymy: An analysis of R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul Minnesota. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 12(2): 211–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Amsterdam, Anthony G., and Jerome Bruner. 2000. Minding the law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cardilli, Riccardo. 1998. Dalla regola romana dell’usura pecuniae in fructu non est agli interessi pecuniari come frutti civili nei moderni codici civili. Roma e America. Diritto Romano Comune 5: 3–54.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Cardilli, Riccardo. 2000. La nozione giuridica di fructus. Napoli: Edizioni Scientifiche italiane.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Falcone, Giuseppe. 2001. Note historique sur la définition législative de la servitude (Article 637 Code Napoléon—Article 1027 Code Civil Italien). Revue Historique de Droit Français et Etranger 79: 13–30.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Guarneri, Attilio. 1974. L’ordine pubblico e il sistema delle fonti del diritto civile. Padova: Cedam.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Teubner, Gunther. 1998. Legal irritants: Good faith in British law or how unifying law ends up in new Divergences. Modern Law Review 61(1): 11–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Ciancio, Anna Giordano. 2005. Fairness in consumer law: A vague, flexible notion. In Vagueness in normative texts, eds. K.Bhatia Vijay et al. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Besen, Stanley M. 1998. Intellectual property. In The new palgrave dictionary of economics, the law, eds. Peter Newman. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Müller, Cornelia. 2008. Metaphors dead and alive, sleeping and waking: A dynamic view. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Chiassoni, Pierluigi. 2006. A nice derangement of literal-meaning freaks: Linguistic contextualism and the theory of legal interpretation. In Analisi e Diritto 2005, eds. Paolo Comanducci and Riccardo Guastini. Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Rumelhart, David, James L. McClelland, and The PDP Research Group. 1987. Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Churchland, Paul M. 1988. The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Recanati, François. 1995. The alleged priority of literal interpretazione. Cognitive Science: A Multidisciplinary Journal XIX(2): 207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Recanati, François. 2004. Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Recanati, François. 2007. Perspectival thought. A plea for (moderate) relativism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Rogers, Timothy T., and James L. McClelland. 2004. Semantic cognition: A parallel distributed processing approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Gazzaniga, Michael S., Bogen, Joseph E., and Roger W. Sperry. 1962. Some functional effects of sectioning the cerebral commissures in man. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 48 Part (2): 1765.

  65. Gazzaniga, Michael S., and Roger W. Sperry. 1967. Language after section of the cerebral commissures. Brain 90(1): 131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Sperry, Roger W., and Michael Gazzaniga. 1967. Language following surgical disconnection of the hemispheres. In Brain mechanisms underlying speech and language, ed. F.L. Darley. New York: Grune and Stratton.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Sperry, Roger W. 1977. Bridging science and values: A unifying view of mind and brain. American Psychologist 32(4): 237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Gazzaniga, Michael S. 2005. The ethical brain. New York: The Dana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Nagel, Thomas. 1971. Brain bisection and the unity of consciousness. Synthese 20: 396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The view from nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Searle, John. 1992. The rediscovery of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Strawson, Galen. 1994. Mental reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Edelman, Gerald M. 1992. Bright air, brilliant fire. On the matter of the brain. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Varela, Francisco J., Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Minsky, Marvin. 1986. The society of mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Dennett, Daniel C. 1969. Content and consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Dennett, Daniel C., and Marcel Kinsbourne. 1992. Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15(2): 183.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Gazzaniga, Michael S. (ed.). 2000. The new cognitive neurosciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Kounios, John, et al. 2008. The origins of insight in resting-state brain activity. Neuropsychologia 46(1): 281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Mark, Jung-Beeman. 2005. Bilateral brain processes for comprehending natural language. Trends in Cognitive Sciences IX(11): 512.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Giora, Rachel. 2003. On our mind: Salience, context, and figurative language. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Taylor, Kirsten I., and Marianne Regard. 2003. Language in the right cerebral hemisphere: Contributions from reading studies. News in Physiological Sciences 18(6): 257.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Taylor, Kirsten I., et al. 1999. Qualitative hemispheric differences in semantic category matching. Brain and Language 70: 119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  84. Jung-Beeman, Mark, et al. 2000. Right and left hemisphere cooperation for drawing predictive and coherence inferences during normal story comprehension. Brain Language 71: 310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  85. Jung-Beeman, Mark, and Christine Chiarello. 1997. Right hemisphere language comprehension: Perspectives from cognitive neuroscience. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc. Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Schmidt, G.L., C.J. DeBuse, and C.A. Seger. 2007. Right hemisphere metaphor processing? Characterizing the lateralization of semantic processes. Brain and Language 100(2): 127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Mashal, Nira, et al. 2005. The role of the right hemisphere in processing nonsalient metaphorical meanings: Application of principal components analysis to fMRI data. Neuropsychologia 43(14): 2084.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  88. Mana, Sotillo, et al. 2005. Neural activity associated with metaphor comprehension: Spatial analysis. Neuroscience Letters 3, 373(1): 5.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Rapp, Alexander M., et al. 2004. Neural correlates of metaphor processing. Cognitive Brain Research 20: 395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  90. Morra, Lucia. 2009. Diritto e metafore: A che punto è la notte? Pólemos 1: 155–175.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Arbib, Michael A. (ed.). 2006. Action to language via the mirror neuron system. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Rizzolatti, Giacomo, and Michael A. Arbib. 1998. Language within our grasp. Trends in Neurosciences 21(5): 188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  93. Arbib, M.A., and Giacomo Rizzolatti. 1997. Neural expectations: A possible evolutionary path from manual skills to language. Communication and Cognition 29: 393.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Bianchi, Claudia (ed.). 2004. The semantics/pragmatics distinction. Stanford: CSLI.

  95. Diciotti, Enrico. 2003. L’ambigua alternativa tra cognitivismo e scetticismo interpretativo. Working paper 45, Università degli Studi di Siena, Dipartimento di scienze storiche, giuridiche, politiche e sociali 3–81.

  96. Guastini, Riccardo. 2008. Interpretazione dei documenti normativi. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Chiassoni, Pierluigi. 1999. La giurisprudenza civile. Metodi d’interpretazione e tecniche argomentative. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Chiassoni, Pierluigi. 2000. ¿Quién salvó a la Constitución? In Analisi e diritto 1999, eds. Paolo Comanducci and Riccardo Guastini. Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Nehaniv, Chrystopher L. (ed.). 1999. Computation for metaphors, analogy and agents. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Indurkhya, Bipin. 1999. An algebraic approach to modeling creativity of metaphor. In Lectures Notes in Computer Science 1562: 292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  101. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2000. The big typescript: TS 213. German–English, Scholar Edition ed. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Dworkin, Ronald M. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Diciotti, Enrico. 2006. Le giustificazioni interpretative nella pratica dell’interpretazione giuridica. Etica & Politica/Ethics and Politics 8. http://www2.units.it/~etica/2006_1/DICIOTTI.htm.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucia Morra.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Morra, L. New Models for Language Understanding and the Cognitive Approach to Legal Metaphors. Int J Semiot Law 23, 387–405 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-010-9163-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-010-9163-z

Keywords

Navigation