Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Computational explanation in neuroscience

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to some philosophers, computational explanation is proprietary to psychology—it does not belong in neuroscience. But neuroscientists routinely offer computational explanations of cognitive phenomena. In fact, computational explanation was initially imported from computability theory into the science of mind by neuroscientists, who justified this move on neurophysiological grounds. Establishing the legitimacy and importance of computational explanation in neuroscience is one thing; shedding light on it is another. I raise some philosophical questions pertaining to computational explanation and outline some promising answers that are being developed by a number of authors.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adrian E.D. (1928). The basis of sensation: The action of the sense organs. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson J.A., Pellionisz A., Rosenfeld E. (1990). Neurocomputing 2: Directions for research. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson J.A., Rosenfeld E. Ed. (1988). Neurocomputing: Foundations of research. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson J.A., Rosenfeld E. Ed. (1998). Talking nets: An oral history of neural networks. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2001). Cognitive neuroscience: Relating neural mechanisms and cognition. In P. Machamer, R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 81–111). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Boden, M. (1991). Horses of a different color? In W. Ramsey et al. (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 3–19). Hillsdale: LEA.

  • Burge T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review 95, 3–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (1996a). Does a rock implement every finite-state automaton? Synthese 108, 310–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (1996b). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland P.S. (1986). Neurophilosophy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland P.S., Koch H., Sejnowski T. (1990). What is computational neuroscience?. In: Schwartz E.L. (eds). Computational neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 46–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland P.S., Sejnowski T.J. (1992). The computational brain. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland B.J. (1996). What is computation?. Synthese 108, 224–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland B.J. (2000). Narrow Versus Wide Mechanism: Including a Re-Examination of Turing’s Views on the Mind-Machine Issue. The Journal of Philosophy XCVI, 5–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane T. (1990). The language of thought: No syntax without semantics. Mind and Language 5(3): 187–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (forthcoming). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Cruse, H. (2001). The explanatory power and limits of simulation models in the neurosciences. In P. , R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 138–154). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Dayan P., Abbott L.F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D.C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown & Co., Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D.C. (2003). Who’s on first? Heterophenomenology explained. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(9–10): 19–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman G.M. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter of the mind. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan F. (1995). Computation and content. Philosophical Review 104, 181–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ericsson K.A. (2003). How to elicit verbal reports that provide valid unobtrusive externalization of concurrent thinking? Journal of Consciousness Studies 10, 9–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Ericsson K.A., Simon H.A. (1993). Protocol analysis. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Feest U. (2003). Functional analysis and the autonomy of psychology. Philosophy of Science 70, 937–948

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1975). The language of thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind–body problem. Scientific American, 244. In J. Heil (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: A guide and anthology (pp. 168–182). Oxford: Oxford University Press (Reprinted 2004).

  • Fodor J.A. (1998). Concepts. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank R.G. (1994). Instruments, nerve action, and the all-or-none principle. Osiris 9, 208–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman W.J. (2001). How brains make up their minds. Columbia Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel C.R. (1990). The organization of learning. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga M.S. Ed. (2000). The new cognitive neurosciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerard, R. W., & Duyff, J. W. (Eds.). (1962) Information processing in the nervous system: Volume III of the international union of physiological sciences (XXII International Congress, Leiden, 1962). Amsterdam: Excerpta Medica Foundation.

  • Globus G.G. (1992). Towards a noncomputational cognitive neuroscience. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 4(4): 299–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A.I. (1997). Science, publicity, and consciousness. Philosophy of Science 64, 525–545

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2001). The semantic challenge to computational neuroscience. In P. Machamer, R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 155–172). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Grush R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27, 377–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffress L.A. Ed. (1951). Cerebral mechanisms in behavior. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird P.N. (1983). Mental models: Towards a cognitive science of language, inference and consciousness. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeley B. (2000). Shocking lessons from electric fish: The theory and practice of multiple realizability. Philosophy of Science 67, 444–465

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd D. (2002). Functional MRI and the study of human consciousness. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 14, 818–831

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan W. (1987). Consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Machtey, M., & Young, P. (1978). An introduction to the general theory of algorithms. New York: North Holland.

  • McClelland J.L., Patterson K. (2002). Rules or connections in past-tense inflections: What does the evidence rule out? Trends in Cognitive Science 6, 465–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch W.S. (1949). The brain as a computing machine. Electrical Engineering 68, 492–497

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch W.S., Pitts W.H. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 7, 115–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller G.A., Galanter E.H., Pribram K.H. (1960). Plans and the structure of behavior. Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A., Simon H.A. (1972). Human problem solving. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A., Simon H.A. (1976). Computer science as an empirical enquiry: and search. Communications of the ACM 19, 113–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C. (1999). Computation as involving content: A response to Egan. Mind and Language 14(2): 195–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perkel D.H. (1990). Computational neuroscience: Scope and structure. In: Schwartz E.L. (eds). Computational neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambrdige, MA, pp. 38–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini G. (2003). Data from introspective reports: Upgrading from commonsense to science. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(9–10): 141–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini G. (2004). The First computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McCulloch and Pitts’s ‘logical calculus of ideas immanent in nervous activity’. Synthese 141(2): 175–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming a). Computationalism, the Church–Turing Thesis, and the Church–Turing Fallacy. Synthese.

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming b). Computational modeling vs. computational explanation: Is everything a Turing machine, and does it matter to the philosophy of mind? Australasian Journal of Philosophy.

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming c). Computational explanation and mechanistic explanation of mind. In M. De Caro, F. Ferretti, & M. Marraffa (Eds.), Cartographies of the mind: The interface between philosophy and cognitive science. Dordrecth: Kluwer.

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming d). Computation without representation. Philosophical Studies.

  • Pinker S., Ullman M. (2002). The past-tense debate: The past and future of the past tense. Trends in Cognitive Science 6, 456–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn Z.W. (1984). Computation and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A. (2001). On the nature of explanation in the neurosciences. In P. Machamer, R. Grush, & P. McLaughlin (Eds.), 2001, Theory and method in the neurosciences (pp. 45–69). University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Rumelhart D.E., McClelland J.M., and the PDP Research Group (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Searle J.R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir O. (2001). Content, computation and externalism. Mind 110(438): 369–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith B.C. (2002). The foundations of computing. In: Scheutz M. (eds). Computationalism: New directions. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 23–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson E., Lutz A., Cosmelli D. (2005). Neurophenomenology: An introduction for neurophilosophers. In: Brook A., Akins K. (eds). Cognition and the brain: The philosophy and neuroscience movement. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 40–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela F. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3(4): 330–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram S. (2002). A new kind of science. Wolfram Media, Champaign, IL

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gualtiero Piccinini.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Piccinini, G. Computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese 153, 343–353 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9096-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9096-y

Keywords

Navigation