Skip to main content
Log in

Temporal Experience: Models, Methodology and Empirical Evidence

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper has two aims. First, to bring together the models of temporal phenomenology on offer and to present these using a consistent set of distinctions and terminologies. Second, to examine the methodologies currently practiced in the development of these models. To that end we present an abstract characterisation in which we catalogue all extant models. We then argue that neither of the two extreme methodologies currently discussed is suitable to the task of developing a model of temporal phenomenology. An entirely top-down methodology is largely insensitive to empirical findings, while one that is entirely bottom-up is insensitive to both introspective evidence and more general philosophical considerations. We recommend a methodology that falls between these two extremes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We assume that level C is continuous—it is characterised by instants of zero duration.

  2. Note that our use of ‘extensionalism’ differs from Dainton’s use. He uses it to delineate a specific model with a temporally extended non-atomic level A, which we fit into our framework below. In contrast, we use this term to refer to a model that has a temporally extended supervenience base.

  3. Other antirealist examples of this mapping are the Humean version of Chuard’s (2011) temporal perceptual atomism and Watzl’s (2013) simple cinematic view.

  4. Another form is an antirealist version of retentionalism. Assuming they have non-extended supervenience bases, examples of this form are Kelly’s (2005a, b) retentionalism and antirealist versions of the following: Chaurd’s (2011) Husserlian temporal perceptual atomism, Watzl’s (2013) retentional view, a version of Lee’s (2014) atomistic view and Phillips’ (2010) memory theory.

  5. Another example of the realist version of this mapping is the top left model depicted in Grush (2007) with a punctuate supervenience base. It is also possible that a version of this falls under Lee’s (forthcoming) ‘atomistic views’. Although he doesn’t give a cinematic example, his characterization allows for this possibility: they have a resulting experience that doesn’t have a C level temporal structure, yet may (or may not) have a content-derived temporal structure, and has a supervenience base that may or (may not) have temporal structure.

  6. For this view to be classified as atomic non-extensionalism, however, the motion of the beam of awareness is not to be considered part of the model. Rather, the moving beam is only invoked to provide temporal relations among such momentary experiences.

  7. For further discussion as to the nature and status of the specious present, see, e.g., Le Poidevin (2007, Ch5) and (2009), Dainton (2010), Kelly (2005a; b), Chuard (2011), Power (2012). Following, e.g., Le Poidevin (2007, 81–82) and Dainton (2010) who both criticise reject Kelly’s and Chuard’s usage of this terminology as referring to a particular model, we assume that the specious present is simply the doctrine defined above and, according to one’s stance, may or may not need to be account for by one’s model.

  8. Other examples of the realist version of this mapping are the content version of Chuard’s (2011) extensional model (AKA ‘the specious present view’), Watzl’s (2013) specious present view, a version of Lee’s (2014) atomistic view, Phillips’ (2010) retentionalist version of specious present theory and his memory theory and, depending on the status of the B level, the bottom left model depicted in Grush (2007).

  9. Other examples of the realist version of this mapping are Lee’s (2014) experiential process view, and, if they have extended supervenience bases, Kelly’s (2005a, b) specious present theory, Chuard’s (2011) structural version of the extensional model, a version of Watzl’s specious present view, the top right and bottom right models depicted in Grush (2007) and the version of Phillips’ (2010) Foster/Dainton specious present theory.

  10. His approach, however, is more complicated than characterized here. For example, he assumes a central principle that relates the B level and A level. This is what he terms the Temporal Identity Principle: Experiences have the same timing as their realizers (2014, 3). However, he uses empirical illusions, experiments and the like in order argue against various strengths of mirroring relations amongst level C external events and level A. Further, he quickly claims that his principle is “very plausible, but won’t argue for it” in his (2014). So, although he assumes a particular principle regarding the relation between level B and level A, it’s not clear exactly what the status of this principle is, i.e., whether it has empirical support or is a mere presupposition.

  11. For an overview of this model and its role in the literature, see Buonomano and Karmarkar (2002), Mauk and Buonomano (2004), Johnston (2010) amongst others. Creelman (1962) and Treisman (1963) are standardly cited as schematizing this model. However, there are several alternative models of duration timing proposed: Grondin (2010) for some such models.

  12. Although this presentation is greatly generalized, it is all that is needed for present purposes. See Treisman (1963, 1984, 1999) for more detail. Also, for discussion of this model in philosophical literature on temporal experience, see Le Poidevin (2007) and Phillips (2012).

  13. Yet, some, e.g., Dainton (2004, 2010), do point out that they are at least aware that different modalities may generate further complexities in their models. However, seldom do they spell out how exactly such differences in modalities may be accommodated. Further, even supposing that such models could be ‘de-centralized’ in this sense, Johnston’s critique of the stopwatch model, as we explicate below, affects another shared feature of these psychological and philosophical models.

  14. It’s a separate question as to whether the same neurons time all intervals or whether, e.g., one set of neurons time 100 ms intervals and another set time 200 ms intervals; these positions are regarded as compatible with both models. In turn, what distinguishes the two models presented above is whether the model is used to time durations experienced by all modalities, or whether the neural pacemaker employed is modality-dependent.

  15. He (2006, 475) also claims to rule out the possibility that, perhaps, there’s a neural timing mechanism corresponding to each hemifield. He does so by rerunning the experiment with the 10 Hz grating being in different regions of the hemifield in which the adaption occurred. The gratings that appear in regions in which the 20 Hz adaptation grating did not occur do not exhibit a marked reduced apparent duration.

  16. For an example of how classic models may offer a general programme for empirical study, see recent work in neurophenomenology. Some of it, e.g., van Gelder (1996), Varela (1996) uses cognitive science to investigate and develop a Husserlian retentionist model. For overviews of this programme, see Grush (2006) and Gallagher (2012).

  17. This definition appears to parallel that of VanRullen.

References

  • Andrews TJ, Purves D, Simpson WA, VanRullen R (2005) The wheels keep turning. Trends Cogn Sci 9(12):560–561

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buonomano DV, Karmarkar UR (2002) How do we tell time? Neuroscientist 8(1):42–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chuard P (2011) Temporal experiences and their parts. Philos Impr 11(11):1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Creelman C (1962) Human discrimination of auditory duration. J Acoust Soc Am 32(582):582–593

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick F, Koch C (2003) A framework for consciousness. Nat Neurosci 6(2):119–126. doi:10.1038/nn0203-119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2000) Stream of consciousness: unity and continuity in conscious experience. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2004) The self and the phenomenal. Ratio 17(4):365–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2008) The experience of time and change. Philos Compass 3(4):619–638

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2010) Temporal consciousness. In Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encylopedia of philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford

  • Dainton B (2011) Time, passage, and immediate experience. In: Callender C (ed) The oxford handbook of philosophy of time. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 382–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagleman DM, Sejnowski TJ (2000) Motion integration and postdiction in visual awareness. Science 287:2036–2038

  • Gallagher S (2012) On the possibility of naturalizing phenomenology. In: Zahavi D (ed) The oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory RL (1966) Eye and brain: the psychology of seeing. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Grondin S (2010) Timing and time perception: a review of recent behavioral and neuroscience findings and theoretical directions. Atten Percept Psychophys 72(3):561–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2006) How to, and how not to, bridge computational cognitive neuroscience and Husserlian phenomenology of time consciousness. Synthese 153(3):417–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush R (2007) Time and experience. In: Muller T (ed) Philosophie der zeit: Neue analytische ansätze. Klostermann, Frankfurt, pp 27–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston A (2010) Modulation of time perception by visual adaptation. In: Nobre AC, Jennifer T (eds) Attention and time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston A, Arnold DH, Nishida S (2006) Spatially localized distortions of event time. Curr Biol 16(5):472–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly SD (2005a) The puzzle of temporal experience. In: Brook A (ed) Cognition and the brain: the philosophy and neuroscience movement. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 208–238

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly SD (2005b) Temporal awareness. In: Smith DW (ed) Phenomenology and philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 222–234

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kline K, Holcombe AO, Eagleman DM (2004) Illusory motion reversal is caused by rivalry, not by perceptual snapshots of the visual field. Vision Res 44(23):2653–2658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (2007) The images of time: an essay on temporal representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (2009) The experience and perception of time. In Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford

  • Lee G (2014) Temporal experience and the temporal structure of experience. Philos Impr 14:1–21

  • Lee G (forthcoming) Atomism, extensionalism and continuity. In Oaklander N (ed) Debates in the metaphysics of time. Bloomsbury: Continuum

  • Mauk MD, Buonomano DV (2004) The neural basis of temporal processing. Annu Rev Neurosci 27(1):307–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips I (2010) Perceiving temporal properties. Eur J Philos 18(2):176–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips I (2012) Attention to the passage of time. Nous Suppl: Philos Perspect 26:277–308

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips I (2014) The temporal structure of experience. In Lloyd D, Arstila V (eds) Subjective time: the philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of temporality. MIT Press

  • Power SE (2012) The metaphysics of the ‘specious’ present. Erkenntnis 77(1):121–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purves D, Paydarfar JA, Andrews TJ (1996) The wagon wheel illusion in movies and reality. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 93(8):3693–3697

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprigge TLS (1983) The vindication of absolute idealism. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman M (1963) Temporal discrimination and the indifference interval: implications for a model of the “internal clock”. American Psychological Association, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman M (1984) Temporal rhythms and cerebral rhythms. Ann NY Acad Sci 423(1):542–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman M (1999) The perception of time: philosophical views and psychological evidence. In: Butterfield J (ed) The arguments of time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1996) Wooden iron? Husserlian phenomenology meets cognitive science. In: Petitot J, Varela F, Pachoud B, Roy J (eds) Naturalizing phenomenology: issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • VanRullen R, Reddy L, Koch C, Purves D (2005) Attention-driven discrete sampling of motion perception. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 102(14):5291–5296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela F (1996) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 3(4):330–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Watzl S (2013) Silencing the experience of change. Philos Stud 165(3):1009–1032

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was partly funded by a John Templeton Foundation grant held by Alex Holcombe, Kristie Miller, Huw Price and Dean Rickles entitled: New Agendas for the Study of Time: Connecting the Disciplines.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Kon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kon, M., Miller, K. Temporal Experience: Models, Methodology and Empirical Evidence. Topoi 34, 201–216 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9251-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9251-x

Keywords

Navigation