Skip to main content
Log in

Thought Experiments in Philosophy: A Neo-Kantian and Experimentalist Point of View

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper addresses the question of the nature and limits of philosophical thought experiments. On the one hand, experimental philosophers are right to claim that we need much more laboratory work in order to have more reliable thought experiments, but on the other hand a naturalism that is too radical is incapable of clarifying the peculiarity of thought experiments in philosophy. Starting from a historico-critical reconstruction of Kant’s concept of the “experiments of pure reason”, this paper outlines an account of thought experiments in philosophy that tries to reconcile the thesis of a principled difference between scientific and philosophical TEs with the position of a methodological naturalism that does not admit any difference in kind between the methods of science and of philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kant’s claim of the purely formal or functional character of the a priori underlies many of the most classical interpretations of his philosophy, be they very critical of this functionality, as for example the idealistic ones, or in accord with it, as in the case of some Neo-Kantian developments and of Trendelenburg’s linguistic reading (which was influenced by the Aristotelian point of view: cf. Trendelenburg 1846).

  2. In this connection reference must also be made to Yiftach Fehige’s neo-Kantian account of TEs (cf. Fehige 2012, 2013, Fehige and Stuart 2014). Unlike Buzzoni, Fehige rejects the universality and necessity of Kant’s a priori, but retains the idea that the a priori, as a constitutive element of the experience, is endowed with a contingent content which may be made explicit by TE. On this point, see Buzzoni 2013b, where Fehige’s account is critically examined.

References

  • Appiah KA (2008) Experimental philosophy. Proc Addresses Am Philos Assoc 82:7–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman W (1927) The logic of modern physics. MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (2011) Laboratory of the mind. Thought experiments in the natural sciences, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno M, Mandelbaum E (2010) Locke’s answer to Molyneux’s thought experiment. Hist Philos Q 27:165–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2008) Thought experiment in the natural sciences. An operational and reflexive-transcendental conception. Königshausen + Neumann, Würzburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2013a) Thought experiments from a Kantian point of view. In: Brown JR, Frappier M, Meynell L (eds) Thought experiments in philosophy, science, and the arts. Routledge, London, pp 90–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2013b) On thought experiments and the Kantian a priori in the natural sciences. A reply to Yiftach. Epistemologia 36:277–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2016–forthcoming) Transcendental philosophy of thought experiments (Kant). In Brown JR, Fehige Y, Stuart M (eds) The Routledge companion to thought experiments. Routledge, London

  • Dancy J (1985) The role of imaginary cases in ethics. Pac Philos Q 66:141–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Little Brown, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2013) Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehige Y (2012) Experiments of pure reason‘. Kantianism and thought experiments in science. Epistemologia 35:141–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehige Y (2013) The relativized a priori and the laboratory of the mind. Towards a neo-Kantian account of thought experiments in science. Epistemologia 36:55–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehige Y, Stuart MT (2014) On the origins of the philosophy of thought experiments. The Forerun. Perspect Sci 22:179–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer E, Collins J (eds) (2015a) Experimental philosophy, rationalism, and naturalism. Rethinking philosophical method. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer E, Collins J (eds) (2015b) Introduction. In: Experimental philosophy, rationalism, and naturalism. Rethinking philosophical method. Routledge, London, p 2–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1964) On knowing what we would say. Philos Rev 73:198–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1992) Kant and the exact sciences. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Baron J (1996) Social roles and the moral judgement of acts and omissions. Eur J Soc Psychol 26:201–218

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R, Wang HT (1999) Setting up a real ‘Chinese Room’: an empirical replication of a famous thought experiment. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 11:153–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Haug MC (ed) (2014) Philosophical methodology: the armchair or the laboratory?. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser L (2002) Nixin’ goes to China. In: Preston J, Bishop M (eds) Views into the Chinese room. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 123–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1989) A function for actual examples in philosophy of science. In: Ruse M (ed) What the philosophy of biology is. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 309–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1950) Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Martinus Nijhoff, Den Haag

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahnemann D (2011) Thinking fast and slow. Doubleday, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalin MG (1972) Kant’s transcendental arguments as Gedankenexperimente. Kant-Studien 63:289–328

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne U (2005) Die Methode des Gedankenexperiments. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M

  • Lichtenberg G Ch (1994) Schriften und Briefe. Zweiter Band. Sudelbücher I. Materialhefte, Tagebücher (ed. by W. Promies). 5th edn. Hanser, München

  • Mach E (1906) Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung, 2nd edn. Barth, Leipzig

  • Mach E (1933) Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwickelung, 9th edn. Brockhaus, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton J (1991) Thought experiments in Einstein’s work. In: Horowitz T, Massey GJ (eds) Thought experiments in science and philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield, Savage, pp 129–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton J (1996) Are thought experiments just what you thought? Can J Philos 26:333–366

    Google Scholar 

  • Ørsted HC (1920[1811]) First introduction to general physics. A prospectus of lectures in this science. In: Jelved K, Jackson AD, Knudsen O (eds) Selected scientific works of Hans Christian Ørsted. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 282–309

  • Peijnenburg J, Atkinson D (2003) When are thought experiments poor ones? J Gen Philos Sci 34:305–322

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H (1902) La science et l’hypothèse. Flammarion, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1972) Conjectures and refutations, 4th edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and Object. M.I.T. Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1965) The theory of relativity and a priori knowledge. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick M (1969) Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926–1936. Olms, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3:417–424

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuart MT (2014) Cognitive science and thought experiments. A refutation of Paul Thagard’s skepticism. Perspect Sci 22:264–287

    Google Scholar 

  • Swain S, Alexander J, Weinberg J (2008) The instability of philosophical intuitions: running hot and cold on truetemp. Philos Phenomenol Res 76:138–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard P (2010) The brain and the meaning of life. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard P (2014) Thought experiments considered harmful. Perspect Sci 22:288–305

    Google Scholar 

  • Trendelenburg A (1846) Geschichte der Kategorienlehre. Bethge, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg JM (2009) On doing better, experimental-style. Philos Stud 145:455–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal KR (2004) Kant’s transcendental proof of realism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes K (1988) Real people. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2007) The philosophy of philosophy. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2009) Replies to Ichikawa, Martin and Weinberg. Philos Stud 145:465–476

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Mike Stuart for many helpful comments and criticisms of an earlier draft of this article. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees for this journal and to the editors of the present issue for a number of useful criticisms and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Buzzoni.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Buzzoni, M. Thought Experiments in Philosophy: A Neo-Kantian and Experimentalist Point of View. Topoi 38, 771–779 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9436-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9436-6

Keywords

Navigation