Skip to main content
Log in

Fictional Characters, Transparency, and Experiential Sharing

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How can providing less textual information about a fictional character make his or her mind more transparent and accessible to the reader? This is the question that emerges from an empirical study of reader response conducted by Kotovych et al. Taking my cue from this study, I discuss the role of implied information in readers’ interactions with characters in prose fiction. This is the textual strategy I call ‘character-centered implicature.’ I argue that the inferential work cued by implicature creates an intersubjective dynamic analogous to what philosophers Zahavi and Rochat discuss under the heading of ‘experiential sharing.’ Effectively, readers complement the textual evocation of mind by drawing on their own past experiences, which leads to a distinctive first-person plural (‘we’) perspective—a sharing of cognitive resources that is responsible for the perceived transparency of the character’s mind. While this experiential sharing may result in empathetic perspective-taking, not all instances of empathy for fictional characters involve sharing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Folk psychology’ refers to the skills we use to make sense of other people’s minds (see Churchland 1991). There is an ongoing debate in the philosophy of mind about those skills, and whether they involve an innate theory of how the mind works (Leslie 1987), internal simulations (Goldman 2006), or a combination of embodied and narrative engagements (Gallagher and Hutto 2008). I won’t enter that debate in this article, but Dan Zahavi’s phenomenologically inspired work—on which I draw in Sect. 3—falls into the third camp.

  2. The term ‘focalization’ was introduced by Gérard Genette in Narrative Discourse (1980), which contains an extensive—and seminal—discussion of internal focalization.

  3. See Grice (1989). The concept of implicature is one of the centerpieces of Sperber and Wilson’s (1995) pragmatic account of language.

  4. Of course, the idea of ‘sharing’ cognitive resources with a fictional being is metaphorical and presupposes the character-centered illusion, or the willingness to approach character mimetically. Cf. the discussion in the opening paragraphs.

  5. Thus, Zahavi and Rochat use the term ‘empathy’ in a different sense from the cognitive or emotional perspective-taking I discussed in the introduction, which is the standard understanding of empathy in discussions of audience-character interactions. In this article, I will not take up Zahavi and Rochat’s phenomenological account of empathy, only their concept of experiential sharing.

  6. Again, as I pointed out in the introduction, I’m not claiming that this coordination underlies readers’ imagination of all characters, but only of those—typically, the protagonists or first-person narrators—whose experiences and mental processes occupy the foreground of a fictional text.

  7. For more on the possibility of ‘consciousness enactment,’ see Caracciolo (2014b, pp. 122–132).

References

  • Caracciolo M (2013) Phenomenological metaphors in readers’ engagement with characters: the case of Ian McEwan’s Saturday. Lang Lit 22(1):60–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2014a) Tell-tale rhythms: embodiment and narrative discourse. Storyworlds 6(2):49–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2014b) The experientiality of narrative: an enactivist approach. de Gruyter, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo M (2016) Strange narrators in contemporary fiction: explorations in readers’ engagement with characters. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll N (2011) On some affective relations between audiences and the characters in popular fictions. In: Coplan A, Goldie P (eds) Empathy: philosophical and psychological perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 162–184

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1991) Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior. In: Greenwood JD (ed) The future of folk psychology: intentionality and cognitive science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 51–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohn D (1978) Transparent minds: narrative modes for presenting consciousness in fiction. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coplan A (2004) Empathic engagement with narrative fictions. J Aesthet Art Crit 62(2):141–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cortázar J (1985) The night face up. In: Blow-up and other stories. Pantheon Books, New York, pp 66–76

  • Eco U (1979) The role of the reader: explorations in the semiotics of texts. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder J (2006) Ways of being close to characters. Film Stud 8:68–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Zahavi D (2008) The phenomenological mind: an introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Hutto DD (2008) Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In: Zlatev J, Racine TP, Sinha C et al (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 17–38

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2001) The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: from mirror neurons to empathy. J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):33–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaut B (1999) Identification and emotion in narrative film. In: Plantinga C, Smith GM (eds) Passionate views: film, cognition, and emotion. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 200–216

    Google Scholar 

  • Genette G (1980) Narrative discourse: an essay in method. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AI (2006) Simulating minds: the philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Iser W (1978) The act of reading: a theory of aesthetic response. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotovych M, Dixon P, Bortolussi M et al (2011) Textual determinants of a component of literary identification. Sci Study Lit 1(2):260–291

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie AM (1987) Pretense and representation: the origins of ‘theory of mind’. Psychol Rev 94(4):412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellmann K (2010) Objects of ‘empathy’: characters (and other such things) as psycho-poetic effects. In: Eder J, Jannidis F, Schneider R (eds) Characters in fictional worlds: understanding imaginary beings in literature, film, and other media. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 416–441

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer A (2004) Fictional minds. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

    Google Scholar 

  • Popova Y (2015) Stories, meaning, and experience. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson D (1989) The garden. In: Journey to paradise: short stories and autobiographical sketches. Virago, London, pp 21–25

  • Shen D (2013) Unreliability. In: Hühn P (ed) The living handbook of narratology. http://www.lhn.uni-hamburg.de/article/unreliability

  • Smith M (1995) Engaging characters: fiction, emotion, and the cinema. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1995) Relevance: communication and cognition. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern DN, Sander LW, Nahum JP et al (1998) Non-interpretive mechanisms in psychoanalytic therapy: the ‘something more’ than interpretation. Int J Psychoanal 79:903–921

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (2009) Qualia. Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/

  • Velleman JD (2003) Narrative explanation. Philos Rev 112(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D, Rochat P (2015) Empathy ≠ sharing: perspectives from phenomenology and developmental psychology. Conscious Cogn 36:543–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This study was funded by the European Research Council (Grant Number 714166).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Caracciolo.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Marco Caracciolo declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Caracciolo, M. Fictional Characters, Transparency, and Experiential Sharing. Topoi 39, 811–817 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9593-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9593-x

Keywords

Navigation