Skip to main content
Log in

The Significance of Fallibilism Within Gettier’s Challenge: A Case Study

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Taking his conceptual cue from Ernest Sosa, John Turri has offered a putative conceptual solution to the Gettier problem: Knowledge is cognitively adept belief, and no Gettiered belief is cognitively adept. At the core of such adeptness is a relation of manifestation. Yet to require that relation within knowing is to reach for what amounts to an infallibilist conception of knowledge. And this clashes with the spirit behind the fallibilism articulated by Gettier when stating his challenge. So, Turri’s form of response is irrelevant to that challenge, which was intended to pose a conceptual problem within fallibilist conceptions of knowledge. (And that failure on Turri’s part needs to be highlighted to remind epistemologists of the need to assess Gettier cases by a fallibilist standard. Although that need was described earlier by Robert Almeder, apparently his advice is being overlooked. This paper develops it anew, in a more general form.)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the original challenge, see Gettier (1963). On the subsequent history of responses to that challenge, see Shope (1983) and Hetherington (2011b).

  2. See, for instance, Williamson (2000: ch. 1) and Hetherington (2010, 2011a: ch. 3).

  3. See Hetherington (forthcoming a).

  4. This is due mainly to Fred Dretske (1970) and Robert Nozick (1981).

  5. On how Gettier cases can be used sceptically, see Hetherington (1996) and Reed (2009).

  6. I base this attribution on personal communication with Turri.

  7. For wider-ranging discussion of fallibilism, see Hetherington (2005) and Fantl and McGrath (2009: ch. 1). Gettier’s own formulation is what Fantl and McGrath call logical fallibilism. They favour instead what they call an epistemic form of fallibilism, mainly a pragmatically imbued one.

  8. For some steps towards a possible solution, see Hetherington (1999, 2011a: ch. 3) and Reed (2002).

  9. For a recent expression of his views on it, see Sosa (2007). For doubts regarding its epistemological power, see Hetherington (forthcoming b).

  10. For an infallibilist answer to the post-Gettier version, see Merricks (1995, 1997).

  11. This talk of non-entailment-of-the-truth-of-the-belief is shared by Almeder’s conception of knowing weakly (1992: 38–9). Beyond that, though, I am offering a more general formulation than he does. His distinction between knowing weakly and knowing strongly is couched in comparatively specific epistemic terms—of evidence being cited, of relevant accessible evidence, and of what other people can say. Now, maybe such ideas would be needed in a finished account; or maybe not. I am making my general points without relying on these particular epistemological commitments. This will help me to adapt my argument to Turri’s and Sosa’s particular form of analysis. They present their supposed solutions to the Gettier problem via a metaphysical picture quite different to the one undergirding the earlier epistemological accounts (e.g. Goldman 1979, 1986, 1988) with which Almeder’s formulation engaged directly.

  12. On whether Gettier’s challenge needs to be solved, see Kaplan (1985). On whether Gettier cases do prove enough to confront us with the Gettier problem, as it is usually interpreted, again see Hetherington (2010, 2011a: ch. 3, forthcoming a).

References

  • Almeder, R. (1992). Blind realism: An essay on human knowledge and natural science. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1970). Epistemic operators. The Journal of Philosophy, 67, 1007–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. S. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge: New studies in epistemology (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1988). Strong and weak justification. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives, vol. 2: Epistemology (pp. 51–69). Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (1996). Gettieristic scepticism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 83–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (1999). Knowing failably. The Journal of Philosophy, 96, 565–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2005). Fallibilism. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/f/fallibil.htm.

  • Hetherington, S. (2010). The Gettier non-problem. Logos & Episteme, 1, 85–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2011a). How to know: A practicalist conception of knowledge. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2011b). The Gettier problem. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 119–130). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (forthcoming a). The Gettier illusion: Gettier-partialism and infallibilism. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9924-6.

  • Hetherington, S. (forthcoming b). There can be lucky knowledge. In M. Steup & J. Turri (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology, 2nd edn. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Kaplan, M. (1985). It’s not what you know that counts. The Journal of Philosophy, 82, 350–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1965). Knowledge, truth, and evidence. Analysis, 25, 168–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (1995). Warrant entails truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55, 841–855.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (1997). More on warrant’s entailing truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, 627–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant: The current debate. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (forthcoming). There cannot be lucky knowledge. In M. Steup & J. Turri (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology, 2nd edn. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107, 143–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2009). A new argument for scepticism. Philosophical Studies, 142, 91–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shope, R. K. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge, vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing full well. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2011). Manifest failure: the Gettier problem solved. Philosophers’ Imprint 11 (April).

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 65–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1999). What is knowledge? In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 92–116). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Hetherington.

Additional information

Thanks to John Turri, and to referees for this journal, for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hetherington, S. The Significance of Fallibilism Within Gettier’s Challenge: A Case Study. Philosophia 40, 539–547 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9340-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9340-7

Keywords

Navigation