Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

An Axiological-Trajectory Theodicy

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I develop a new theodicy in defense of Anselmian theism, one that has several advantages over traditional and recent replies to the Problem of Evil. To make my case, I first explain the value of a positive trajectory: a forward-in-time decrease in ‘first-order-gratuitous’ evil: evil that is not necessary for any equal-or-greater first-order good, but may be necessary for a higher-order good, such as the good of strongly positive axiological trajectory. Positive trajectory arguably contributes goodness to a world in proportion to the magnitude of this trajectory, and worlds that contain first-order-gratuitous evil thereby have the potential to contain a strongly positive trajectory. This would arguably explain why God would permit first-order-gratuitous evils: he may be indifferent between a world with no first-order-gratuitous evil (and thus a flat trajectory) and a world with some first-order-gratuitous evil but a strongly positive trajectory. Next, I answer the most salient objections to this theodicy. Finally, I explain how this theodicy is superior to some common theodicies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mackie (1955: 200) and Rowe (1979: 335), on the first pages of their landmark articles, indicate that they are targeting Anselmian theism.

  2. Most philosophers are at-least-sympathetic to the core of the Problem of Evil; cf. Bourget and Chalmers 2014: 476. I assume that if most philosophers are atheists, then at-least-most philosophers are at-least-sympathetic to the Problem of Evil.

  3. A first-order good is a good that is not in itself about distributions or magnitudes of goodness or evil; see below.

  4. Strictly speaking, Leftow (2013) could count as what I’m calling a ‘radical,’ not a ‘theodicist,’ but I view him as at theodicist because he is explaining why it would be morally imperfect for God to prevent some evils. In any case, not much turns on this distinction in the rest of my paper.

  5. In Mackie’s (1955), he argues that God would have prevented any evil at all. Therefore, he regards all evils as gratuitous.

  6. Perhaps the world itself is a Moorean organic unity. Moore (1993 [1903]: 78 ff.). I am grateful to an anonymous referee for noting this.

  7. Compare Ross’s (1939: 138) two worlds.

  8. If positive trajectory in well-being across a life is important (cf. Kazez 2007: 74 ff.), then this may provide a third reason to suspect that positive trajectory of a world is axiologically valuable. I lack the space to explore this possibility here.

  9. To be sure, there are well-known riches-to-rags stories, such as in Greek tragedies. However, philosophers usually view the value of these not in esthetic terms per se, but in didactic terms (Aristotle, Poetics, 1449b). The lives themselves aren’t good, and do not clearly contribute to the goodness of the world, but our inspecting such lives makes the rest of us more virtuous. Still, this would presumably be a value of a rags-to-riches world as well.

  10. An Anselmian God is omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect, among other properties. See, e.g., Anselm 2001 [1077–78]: ch. V. His moral perfection would lead him to want to actualize the overall-best set of values. I do not need to take a position here on whether these values are ultimately commensurable or reducible to each other; all I need is that esthetic goodness is genuinely valuable.

  11. If it’s ever permissible to spend money on art instead of on famine-relief, then, I think, we can say that the values are commensurable. Cf. Singer 1972, and Kagan 1989: 3 ff. on moral options: points at which it is at-least-permissible to do what is non-optimific. I say ‘most’ philosophers because presumably, nearly all deontologists, plus some consequentialists (e.g., scalar consequentialists (Norcross 1997)), will believe in options.

  12. See e.g. Henderson et al. for a defense of nonconciliation or steadfastness.

  13. Penner 2006; Howard-Snyder and Howard-Snyder 1994; Rowe 2004: 112. If no-best-world or other a priori atheological arguments are sound, then my theodicy is otiose anyway. And if the Problem of Evil can be rebutted by adverting to a non-traditional Anselmianism (Almeida 2012), then my theodicy is also otiose. Therefore, I set aside such concerns. There are of course interesting reasons to dispute this assumption, or at least its alleged implications (Murphy 2017), but I lack the space to discuss them here, especially given that they would likely obviate my theodicy anyway.

  14. Strictly speaking, if the amount of first-order-gratuitous evil in these moments decreases in the right way, the total may be finite, in the way that 1 + ½ + ¼ + … = 2. But this is a priori very improbable.

  15. Galor and Moav 2007; Galor and Moav 2005; World Bank Group 2017; World Bank Group 2016: 12.

  16. Cf. the examples in Huemer 2015: § 3.

  17. E.g. Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka, 347 U. S. 483 (1954); Davis 1984; Langley 1999; Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U. S. 558 (2003).

  18. See e.g. Pinker 2011.

  19. Democracy in which a high proportion of the citizenry is eligible to vote is rare historically. See e.g. Dahl et al. 2003; Huntington 1996.

  20. Again, see also Norberg 2016 for a useful survey of all the ways in which the world is on a positive axiological-trajectory.

  21. Data from Bourget and Chalmers (2014: 479) note a strong positive-correlation between consequentialism and naturalism, and data on the survey site they link confirm the negative correlation between theism and consequentialism.

References

  • Adams, M. M. C. (1988). Theodicy without blame. Philosophical Topics, 16(2), 215–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almeida, M. J. (2012). Freedom, god, and worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anselm (2001). [1077-78]. Proslogion, with the Replies of Gaunilo and Anselm. Tr. Thomas Williams. Indianapolis and Cambridge : Hackett Publishing Co.

  • Aquinas, T. (1948). The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas. Tr. Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York: Benziger Brothers.

  • Barro, R., & Lee, J.-W. (2013). A new data set of educational attainment in the world, 1950-2010. Journal of Development Economics, 104, 184–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. J. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. B. (1984). Slavery and human Progress. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeYoung, R. K., McCluskey, C., & Van Dyke, C. (2009). Aquinas’s ethics: Metaphysical foundations, moral theory, and theological content. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galor, O., & Moav, O. (2005). “Natural selection and the evolution of life expectancy.” Brown University Working Papers, URL = <http://sticerd.lse.ac.uk/seminarpapers/dg09102006.pdf>.

  • Galor, O., & Moav, O. (2007). “The Neolithic revolution and contemporary variations in life expectancy.” Brown University Working Papers, URL = <https://www.brown.edu/academics/economics/sites/brown.edu.academics.economics/files/uploads/2007-14_paper.pdf>.

  • Hick, J. (1977). Evil and the god of love, 2nd ed. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holtug, N. (1998). Egalitarianism and the levelling down objection. Analysis, 58(2), 166–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, D., & Howard-Snyder, F. (1994). How an unsurpassable being can create a Surpassable world. Faith and Philosophy, 11(2), 260–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, D., & Howard-Snyder, F. (1999). Is theism compatible with gratuitous evil? American Philosophical Quarterly, 36(2), 115–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2015). A Liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: The empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983–2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Progress. (2016). “Human Progress.” URL = <http://humanprogress.org> Accessed 13 Oct 2016.

  • Huntington, S. P. (1996). Democracy’s third wave. In L. Diamond & M. F. Plattner (Eds.), The global resurgence of democracy (pp. 3–25). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kazez, J. (2007). “Necessities.” In Jean Kazez, The Weight of Things: Philosophy and the Good Life (Malden: Blackwell), pp. 61–80.

  • Kraay, K. J. (2010). Theism, possible worlds, and the multiverse. Philosophical Studies, 147(3), 355–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraay, K. J. (Ed.). (2015). God and the multiverse: Scientific, philosophical, and theological perspectives. New York and Milton Park: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronen, J., & Reitan, E. (2013). God’s final victory: A comparative case for universalism. New York and London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langley, W. (1999). Encyclopedia of human rights issues since 1945. Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leftow, B. (2013). God’s deontic perfection. Res Philosophica, 90(1), 69–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lembke, M. (2013). Whatever it is better to be than not to be. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 74(1), 131–143.

  • Mackie, J. L. (1955). Evil and omnipotence. Mind, 64(254), 200–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1993) [1903]. Principia Ethica, revised edition (ed. Thomas Baldwin). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Murphy, M. C. (2017). God’s own ethics: Norms of divine agency and the argument from evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Norberg, J. (2016). Progress: Ten reasons to look forward to the future. London: Oneworld Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (1997). Good and bad actions. Philosophical Review, 106(1), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2002). Equality or priority? In M. Clayton & A. Williams (Eds.), The ideal of equality (pp. 81–125). Houndmills and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penner, M. A. (2006). Divine creation and perfect goodness in a ‘no best world’ scenario. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 59(1), 25–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: Why violence has declined. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1977). God, freedom, and evil. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2004). Supralapsarianism, or ‘O Felix Culpa. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Christian Faith and the Problem of Evil (pp. 1–25). Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2008). “Reply to Tooley’s opening statement.” In Alvin Plantinga and Michael Tooley, Knowledge of God (Malden: Blackwell Publishing): 151–83.

  • Pritt, S. (2015). Spotlight on animal welfare. ALN Magazine, 14(3), 23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, B. (1976). Natural evils and natural Laws: A theodicy for natural evils. International Philosophical Quarterly, 16(2), 179–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1939). Foundations of ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. L. (1979). The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 6(4), 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. L. (2004). Can god be free? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sala-i-Martin, X., & Pinkovskiy, M. (2009). “Parametric estimations of the world distribution of income.” In NBER Working Paper Series, URL = <http://www.nber.org/papers/w15433>.

  • Schabas, W. A. (2011). An introduction to the international criminal court. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation: A new ethics for our treatment of animals. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (1985). Suffering for redemption: A reply to smith. Faith and Philosophy, 2(4), 392–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (2018). “The problem of evil.” In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Summer 2018 edition, URL =< https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/evil/>.

  • Trakakis, N. (2007). The god beyond belief: In Defence of William Rowe’s evidential argument from evil. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1988). The magnitude, duration, and distribution of evil: A theodicy. Philosophical Topics, XIV(2), 161–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2006). The problem of evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1977). Just and unjust wars. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstock, J. A. (1974). What theodicies must, but do not, do. Philosophia, 4(4), 449–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woollard, F. (2012). The doctrine of doing and allowing I: Analysis of the doing/allowing distinction. Philosophy Compass, 7(7), 448–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Bank Group. (2016). Global monitoring report 2015/2016: Development goals in an era of demographic change. Washington, DC: World Bank Group and The International Monetary Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wykstra, S. J. (1984). The human obstacle to evidential arguments from suffering: On avoiding the evils of ‘appearance. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 16(2), 73–94.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to editors and anonymous referees for this journal for their very helpful comments. I would also like to thank attendees at the 2017 meeting of the Alabama Philosophical Society for their comments on this paper. Finally, I would like to thank Rachel Rupprecht for her comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Metcalf.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Metcalf, T. An Axiological-Trajectory Theodicy. SOPHIA 59, 577–592 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-019-00747-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-019-00747-7

Keywords

Navigation