Skip to main content
Log in

The Challenges Involved with Going Negative

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One rather common way of doing philosophy involves what is called “the method of cases,” where philosophers design hypothetical cases and use what we think about those cases—our “philosophical intuitions”—as evidence that certain philosophical theories are true or false, and as reasons for believing that those theories are true or false. This way of doing philosophy has been challenged in recent years on the basis of both general epistemological considerations and more specific methodological concerns. These methodological concerns have focused not on whether philosophical intuitions can be a good source of evidence, but rather on whether they can be used in the ways that they currently are used in actual philosophical practice given how little we know about them and some of the worrisome things that we have learned about them in recent years. My goal here is to provide you with a short introduction to this way of challenging to how philosophers use the method of cases, and to walk you through some of the more popular ways of responding to this kind of methodological challenge and some of their shortcomings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alexander, J. (2010). Is experimental philosophy philosophically significant? Philosophical Psychology, 23, 331–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy: An introduction. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. (2016a). Philosophical expertise. In W. Buckwalter & J. Sytsma (Eds.), Companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 557–567). New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. (2016b). Thought experiments, mental models, and experimental philosophy. In J. Nado (Ed.), Advances in experimental philosophy and philosophical methodology (pp. 53–68). New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. (2010). Accentuate the negative. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 297–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. (2007). Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 2, 56–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. (2014). The “unreliability” of epistemic intuitions. In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy (pp. 128–145). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (1998). Intuition and the autonomy of philosophy. In M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition (pp. 201–240). Latham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2013). Experimental attacks on intuitions and answers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 495–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy without intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2014). Intuitions in philosophy: A minimal defense. Philosophical Studies, 17, 535–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, S. (2013). Intuitions as evidence, philosophical expertise and the development challenge. Philosophical Papers, 42, 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cullen, S. (2010). Survey-driven romanticism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 275–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1998). Reflections on reflective equilibrium. In M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition (pp. 113–128). Latham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demaree-Cotton, J. (2016). Do framing effects make moral intuitions unreliable? Philosophical Psychology, 29, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, M. (2010). Intuitions, counter-examples, and experimental philosophy. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 447–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, M. (2015). The myth of the intuitive: Experimental philosophy and philosophical method. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2007). Philosophical intuitions: Their target, their source, and their epistemic status. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, T. (2010). Some hope for intuitions: A reply to Weinberg. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 481–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. (2006). Relativism and the foundations of philosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2010). How (not) to react to experimental philosophy. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 447–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations, 10, 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its place in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2010). What reflective endorsement cannot do. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, J. (2005). The evidential status of philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies, 121, 193–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. M., Wiegmann, A., Alexander, J., & Vong, G. (2012). Putting the trolley in order: Experimental philosophy and the loop case. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 661–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T. (2009). The role of moral commitments in moral judgment. Cognitive Science, 33, 273–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2007). The epistemology of thought experiments: First person versus third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 128–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2011). Thought experiments and philosophical knowledge. Metaphilosophy, 42, 191–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2012). Expertise and intuitions about reference. Theoria, 27, 37–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., Sirker, S., Naoki, U., & Hashimoto, T. (2017, forthcoming). Gettier was framed! In M. Mizumoto, E. McCready, & Stich, S. (Eds.), Epistemology for the rest of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Nadelhoffer, T., & Feltz, A. (2008). The actor-observer bias and moral intuitions: Adding fuel to Sinnott-Armstrong’s Fire. Neuroethics, 1, 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nado, J. (2014). Philosophical expertise. Philosophy Compass, 9, 631–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nado, J. (2015a). Philosophical expertise and scientific expertise. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 1026–1044.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nado, J. (2015b). Intuition, philosophical theorizing, and the threat of skepticism. In E. Fischer & J. Collins (Eds.), Experimental philosophy, rationalism, and naturalism: Rethinking philosophical method (pp. 204–221). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nado, J. (2016). The intuition deniers. Philosophical Studies, 173, 781–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2000). Intuitions as evidence. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. (2013). Analogies, moral intuitions, and the expertise defense. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5, 169–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryberg, J. (2012). Moral intuitions and the expertise defense. Analysis, 73, 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz, E., Cokely, E., & Feltz, A. (2011). Persistent bias in expert judgments about free will and moral responsibility: A test of the expertise defense. Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 1722–1731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language, 27, 135–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2015). Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise and reflection. Cognition, 141, 127–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Framing moral intuitions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology. The cognitive science of morality—Intuition and diversity (Vol. 2, pp. 47–76). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies, 132, 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1988). Reflective equilibrium, analytic epistemology, and the problem of cognitive diversity. Synthese, 74, 391–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. (2008). The instability of philosophical intuitions: Running hot and cold on truetemp. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 138–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1985). The trolley problem. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36, 359–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2013). Moral intuitions: Are philosophers experts? Philosophical Psychology, 26, 629–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. (2007). How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 318–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. (2014). Cappelen between a rock and a hard place. Philosophical Studies, 17, 517–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., & Alexander, J. (2014). The challenge of sticking with intuitions through thick and thin. In A. Booth and D. Rowbottom (Eds.), Intuition (pp. 187–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Weinberg, J., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology, 23, 331–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. New York: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Alexander.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alexander, J. The Challenges Involved with Going Negative. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 34, 465–479 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0118-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0118-6

Keywords

Navigation