Skip to main content
Log in

Explanations at Multiple Levels1

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The preference for `reductive explanations', i.e., explanations of the behaviour of a system at one `basic' level of sub-systems, seems to be related, at least in the physical sciences, to the success of a formal technique –- perturbation theory –- for extracting insight into the workings of a system from a supposedly exact but intractable mathematical description of the system. This preference for a style of explanation, however, can be justified only in the case of `regular' perturbation problems in which the zeroth-order term in the perturbation expansion (characterizing the `basic' level) is the uniform limit of the exact solution as the perturbation parameter goes to zero. For the much more frequent case of `singular' perturbation problems, various techniques have been developed which all introduce a hierarchy of levels or scales into the solutions. These levels describe processes or sub-systems operating simultaneously at different time or spatial scales. No single level, no reductive explanation in the above sense will provide an adequate explanation of the system behaviour. Explanations involving multiple levels should be recognized as far more common even in supposedly reductionist disciplines like physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson, P.W. (1997 [1984]), Basic Notions of Condensed Matter Physics, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. (1995), 'Theories between Theories: Asymptotic Limiting Intertheoretic Relations', Synthese 103, pp. 171–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. (1997), “'Into a Mist”: Asymptotic Theories on a Caustic', Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28, pp. 395–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. (2000), 'A “Modern” (=Victorian?) Attitude Towards Scientific Understanding', Monist 83, pp. 228–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. and Richardson, R.C. (1992), 'Emergent Phenomena and Complex Systems', in A. Beckermann et al., eds., Emergence or Reduction? Berlin: DeGruyter, pp. 257–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (1998), Psychoneural Reduction, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ene, H.I. and Polisevski, D. (1987), Thermal Flow in Porous Media, Dordrecht: D.Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedrichs, K.O. (1955), 'Asymptotic Phenomena in Mathematical Physics', Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 61, pp. 485–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guckenheimer, J. and Holmes, P. (1983), Nonlinear Oscillators, Dynamical Systems, and Bifurcations of Vector Fields, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinch, E.J. (1990), Perturbation Methods, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffreys, H. and Jeffreys, B. (1962), Methods of Mathematical Physics (3rd edition), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kokotovic, P.V. (1987), 'Singular Perturbation Techniques in Control Theory', in P.V. Kokotovic et al., eds., Singular Perturbations and Asymptotic Analysis in Control Systems, Berlin: Springer, pp. 1–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon, K. and Charles, D. (1992), 'Introduction', in K. Lennon and D. Charles, eds., Reduction, Explanation, and Realism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, D. (1981), 'Investigations of the Concept of Reduction II', Erkenntnis 16, pp. 109–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985), 'Galilean Idealization', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16, pp. 247–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1973), 'Two Concepts of Inter-Theoretic Reduction', Journal of Philosophy 70, pp. 181–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primas, H. (1983), Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics, and Reductionism, Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975), 'Philosophy and Our Mental Life', in H. Putnam, Mind, Language, and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 291–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, J. (1995), 'Construction by Reduction', Philosophy of Science 62, pp. 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redhead, M.L.G. (1980), 'Models in Physics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31, pp. 145–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A. (2000), 'Physical Emergence, Diachronic and Synchronic', Synthese 124, pp. 297–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, A. and Sharp, W.D. (1998), 'Idealization and Stability: A Perspective from Nonlinear Dynamics', in N. Shanks, ed., Idealization IX: Idealization in Contemporary Physics, Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 201–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanchez-Palencia, E. (1980), Non-Homogeneous Media and Vibration Theory, Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1992), 'Models of Reduction and Categories of Reductionism', Synthese 91, pp. 167–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D.R. (1985), Singular Perturbation Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rueger, A. Explanations at Multiple Levels1. Minds and Machines 11, 503–520 (2001). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1011847713834

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1011847713834

Keywords

Navigation