Skip to main content

The Difficulty of Assessing Quality or Quality-of-Life

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Quality
  • 1498 Accesses

Abstract

The quality of human existence is becoming an increasingly visible and vocal political and social concern. Yet, many of the approaches to this problem do not include a discussion of how the judgment of quality itself is made. This book addresses this issue describing an approach that relies on examining the language used and the cognitive processes involved in a qualitative judgment and assessment. This chapter provides the background to this effort, and describes issues in the assessment of quality-of-life or health-related quality-of-life that once clarified will lead to a model of how a qualitative judgment occurs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The terms, quality, quality-of-life and HRQOL will be distinguished throughout this book. The term “quality,” or the phrase “qualitative assessment,” will be the most general form of expression, referring to all types of qualitative assessments. As stated in the Preface, I will use the term “qualitative” to refer to those instances involving the judgment of quality, and not limit it to a set of qualitative, as opposed to psychometric, methods. There are phrases, such as “qualitative research” which refer to a particular research orientation, but my use of the term “qualitative” refers to a class of judgments and not these methods. Of course, qualitative judgments can be studied using both qualitative and psychometric research approaches.

    The phrase “quality-of-life” will be differentiated from the phrase “HRQOL” in that one refers to the general population, while the other refers to persons who are medically or psychiatrically ill.

  2. 2.

    The distinction being made here, whether quality-of-life is a reflection of a person’s current state or a basis for future action or decisions, is an important one that is often overlooked by investigators. If a quality or quality-of-life assessment is a reflection of a person’s past or current state, then it need not lead to action or a decision, but action or a decision will usually imply a projection of a person’s future quality-of-life. This, I suggest, is an important difference between a standard quality-of-life assessment and a utilities-based assessment of quality-of-life (see Torrance et al. 1995) that may encompass the past and current state but also project to the future.

  3. 3.

    The SF-36 is a shorter version (36 items) of a questionnaire originally developed at the Rand Corporation, by John Ware and his colleagues as part of the Medical Outcome Study.

  4. 4.

    Clearly, there are medical, political and religious conditions under which a person will have limited or no opportunity to decide what is best for themselves. However, in many of these instances a person will be able to participate in these decisions if given the opportunity. This issue has been previously discussed in a medical care context (Barofsky 2003).

  5. 5.

    Implicit in this statement is the belief that no man is wise enough to capture all of the thoughts, wishes and values of all people and that only empirical observation will provide the reassurance that the relevant data have been approximated by an appropriate measure of quality-of-life or HRQOL. I will address this issue again when I speak about Hayek’s contribution to the assessment of quality (Chap. 3).

  6. 6.

    Wittgenstein provides some examples of a language game; for example, giving orders and obeying them, describing an object and giving its assessment, speculating about an event, presenting the results of an experiment in tables, making up a story and reading it, guessing riddles, asking, thanking, cursing, greeting and praying are all examples of language games (Wittgenstein 1953; p. 11–12).

  7. 7.

    Daston and Galison (2007; p. 168) point out that the idea of “family resemblance” came from the early work of Galton who traced the images of members of a family and then generated a composite representation of the entire family. Galton labeled this composite a “family resemblance,” which it literally was. Wittgenstein also attended the Vienna group of logical positivists where he was exposed to current psychological research on psychophysics.

  8. 8.

    It is useful to review the relationship between Hume and Wittgenstein, since both contend that “some truths or realities are created by our linguistic practices” (Bloor 1996; p. 356). The extent to which this notion can be extended to a quality assessment, which is based on a “linguistic practice,” is something I will be concerned about throughout this book.

  9. 9.

    It is also possible that a culture exists where a person may not have any experience with attaching numbers to feelings or other types of states. This would only be relevant if it could also be demonstrated that the members of this culture could not learn to do this task. If this were so, then these people would join the large group of challenged persons who remain an unresolved task for quality-of-life assessment.

  10. 10.

    This discussion will focus mostly on the single global self-assessed items, including the SAHS or self-assessed quality-of-life items. I do this because the global items come closest to approximating the experiential and cognitive origins of a qualitative assessment. Understanding how an impression of quality emerges will be a key element in the approach to be discussed. I have already hinted at how this might occur as the non-linear emergence of a complex cognitive entity.

  11. 11.

    The SAHS item is sometimes referred to as a quality-of-life self-report, but this would be a clear example of using the phrase “quality-of-life” as a label, since the item is a descriptive statement which lacks the valuation component needed for a complete qualitative indicator. I will review the literature that deals with the SAHS item, since it is particularly complete, but the item itself is most accurately considered a health status indicator.

  12. 12.

    In Chap. 8, I make clear how a health status and HRQOL item differ. The information summarized in this chapter is actually more about the value of a single global health status item, but is not informative about whether a single global quality-of-life item is a good predictor of mortality.

  13. 13.

    Sometimes multi-item assessments include global self-report items along with domain-specific items. In this case, it may be possible to disaggregate the multi-item assessment and study the single global self-report item separately.

  14. 14.

    Accessed at the Wikipedia website (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Qualia; last modified 5/4/2006; accessed 5/31/2006).

  15. 15.

    Accessed at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy website (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia/; accessed 5/31/2006).

  16. 16.

    A linear model would state that what I experience when I report seeing something involves having me receive a visual input followed by the activation of the visual cortex leading to some visual experience. A non-linear model could involve the reprocessing of the visual input in such a way that what I experience is not necessarily predicted by the physical characteristics of the stimulus (e.g., Miichotte 1968), but involve other cognitive processes.

  17. 17.

    A Turning Machine provides a set of instructions (e.g., an algorithm) presented in symbolic form that relates the input and output of some system. Thus, a Turing Machine output is computation.

  18. 18.

    Clearly there are cognitive processes that I may not be aware of, such as appraisal, which may influence what I am aware of, but in this context I am not dealing with all the factors that might determine what I am aware of, only those qualities that I have already attached to the experience.

  19. 19.

    Phaedrus, a character from Plato’s writings, is used by Pirsig (1974) as a “literary devise” and Richardson (2008; p. 11) claims that Pirsig used Phaedrus to express his own views.

  20. 20.

    In Chap. 6, I introduce the notion that people process information in two basic ways: automatically or after due consideration. Dual processing of this sort may yet account for the difference between aesthetic and functional quality. For this to be confirmed will require clarification of the relation of emotions and cognition to determine which comes first, who influences whom and so on. These issues will be discussed in Chap. 11.

  21. 21.

    An example of a preventative practice that is not widespread and would have a qualitative consequence, is assessing quality-of-life during a Phase I clinical trial.

  22. 22.

    Physicians engage in many activities that are designed to ensure quality control. Medical case conferences, in which specific cases are discussed, would be one example of a quality control effort. Another example is the procedure a department of surgery established to prevent “wrong site, wrong procedure and wrong patient outcomes” (Michaels et al. 2007). Quality control activities, however, does not ensure that the patient has an optimal qualitative outcome. Thus, when I discuss quality control there are multiple levels of application.

  23. 23.

    As is often the case, some other author previously stated the same basic idea. Robert Pirsig in his book “Lila” (1991) ends it by stating the following:

    Good is a noun. That was it. That was what Phaedrus had been looking for. That was the homer, over the fence, that ended the ball game. Good is a noun rather than an adjective is all that the Metaphysics of Quality is about. Of course, the ultimate Quality isn’t a noun or adjective or anything else definable, but if you had to reduce the whole Metaphysics of Quality to a single sentence, that would be it (p. 409).

    Each individual, community, or nation doing good – making quality a primary objective of their activities – is what is required for ethical outcomes.

  24. 24.

    Paul Kind (October 2005, personal communication) has indicated that Rachel Rosser’s husband was an operations researcher and he felt that his background influenced the model that was developed.

  25. 25.

    Matching the expectations of a buyer is not a simple process, since a person’s expectation may not be in concordance with the manufacturer’s estimate of the cost of the product. There is obviously an entire topic of interest here, the ethics of material exchange.

  26. 26.

    I use the word “entity” to refer to the subjective experience I am assessing, since the quale has become infused with the mind–body debate and I want to avoid implying that what will be presented supports a dualistic perspective. In fact, in Chap. 10 I provide several examples of how mind–body or capacity–performance dichotomies can be presented in non-dualistic terms.

Abbreviations

EQ-5D:

EuroQual-5 Dimensions (Brooks et al. 2003)

HRQOL:

Health-related quality-of-life

SAHS:

Self assessed health status

TMS:

Transcranial magnet stimulation

References

  • Ackoff RL. (1976). Does quality of life have be quantified? Oper Res Q. 27,280–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aksoy S. (2000). Can the “quality of life” be used as a criterion in health care services? Bull Med Ethics. October 19–22, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albin JM. (1992). Quality Improvement in Employment and Other Human Services: Managing for Quality Through Change. Baltimore MD: Brookes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anthony T, Hyman LS, Rosen D, Kim L, et al. (2003). The association of pretreatment health-related quality of life with surgical complications for patients undergoing open surgical resection for colorectal cancer. Ann Surg. 238, 690–696.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Barofsky I. (2003). Cognitive approaches to summary measurement: Its application to the measurement of diversity in health-related quality of life assessments. Qual Life Res. 12, 251–260.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Barofsky I, Erickson P, Eberhardt M. (2004). Comparison of multi-item and self-assessed health status (SAHS) indexes among persons with and without diabetes in the U.S. Qual Life Res. 13, 1671–1681.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Barofsky I and Sugarbaker PH. (1990). The cancer patient. In, (Ed) B Spilker. Quality of life Assessment in Clinical Studies. New York NY: Raven. (p. 419–439).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benyamini Y, Idler EL. (1999). Community studies reporting association between self-rated health and mortality: Additional studies, 1995 to 1998. Res Aging. 21, 392–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim JL. (1999). How to get serious answers to the serious question: “How have you been?”: Subjective quality of life (QOL) as an individual experiential emergent construct. Bioeth. 13, 272–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blazeby JM, Brookes ST, Alderson D. (2001). The prognostic value of quality of life scores during treatment for oesophageal cancer. Gut. 49, 227–230.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Blazeby JM, Metcalfe C, Nicklin J, Barham CP, et al. (2005). Association between quality of life scores and short -term outcome after surgery for cancer of the oesophagus or gastric cardia. Brit J Surg. 92, 1502–1507.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor D. (1996). The question of linguistic idealism revisited. In, (Eds) H Sluga, DG Stern. The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. New York NY: Cambridge University Press. (p. 354–382).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman PW. (1959). The Way Things Are. New York NY: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brod M, Stewart A, Sands L, Walton P. (1999). Conceptualization and measurement of quality of life in dementia: the Dementia Quality of life Instrument (DQOL). Gerontol. 39, 25–35.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks R, Rabin R, de Charro F. (2003). The Measurement and Valuation of Health Status Using the EQ-5D: A European Perspective. Evidence from the EurQol BIOMED Research Programme. Dordrecht The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burbules NC, Peters M. (2007). Tractarian Pedagogies: Sense and nonsense. Retrieved on the Web, 2/8/2007. http://www.faculty.ed.uiuc.edu/burbules/syllabi/Materials/tip.html.

  • Campbell, N. R. (1928). An Account of the Principles of Measurement and Calculation. London UK: Longmans, Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell A, Converse PE, Rodgers WL. (1976). The Quality of American Life. New York NY: Russell Sage Foundation- Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantril H. (1965). The Pattern of Human Concerns. New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cattorini P, Mordacci R. (1994). Happiness, life and quality of life: A commentary on Nordenfelt’s “Towards a Theory of Happiness”. In, (Ed.) L Nordenfelt. Concepts and Measurement of Quality of life in Health Care. Dordrecht The Netherlands: Kluwer. (p. 59–62).

    Google Scholar 

  • Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC). (2000).Measuring Healthy Days: Population Assessment of Health Related Quality of life. Atlanta GA: Center for Disease Control.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A. (1993). Sensory Qualities. Oxford UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cloninger CR. (2004). Feeling Good: The Science of Well-Being. New York NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins RA. (1996). The domains of life satisfaction: An attempt to order chaos. Soc Indic Res. 38, 303–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins RA. (2000). Objective and subjective quality of life: An interactive model. Soc Indics Res. 52. 55–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cytowic RE. (2002). Touching tastes, seeing smells- and shaking up brain science. The Dana Forum Brain Sci. 14,7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York NY: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston L, Galison P. (2007). Objectivity. New York NY: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Boer AGEM, van Lanschot JJB, Stalmeier PFM, van Sandick JW, et al. (2003). Is a single item visual analogue scale as valid, reliable and responsive as multi-item scales in measuring quality of life? Qual Life Res. 13, 311–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC. (1988). Quining qualia. In, (Eds.) A Marcel, E Bisiach. Consciousness in Contemporary Science. New York NY: Oxford University Press. (p. 42–77).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston MA: Little, Brown and Company. (p.369–411).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC. (1995). Review of Damasio, Descartes’ Error. Times Literary Suppl. August 25, 1995. (p 3–4).

    Google Scholar 

  • Efficace F, Bottomley A, Coens C, Van Steen K, et al. (2006). Does a patient’s self-reported health-related quality of life predict survival beyond key biomedical data in advanced colorectal cancer? Eur J Cancer. 42, 42–49.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Faden R, Leplege A. (1992). Assessing quality of life: Moral implications for clinical practice. Med Care 30 Suppl, MS166-MS175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fanshel S, Bush, JW. (1970). A Health Status Index and its application to the health services outcomes. Oper Res. 18, 1021–1066.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fayers PM, Machin D. (2000). Quality of life: Assessment, Analysis and Interpretation. Chichester UK: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinstein AR. (1987a). Clinimetric perspective. J Chronic Dis. 40, 635–640.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Feinstein AR. (1987b). Clinimetrics. New Haven CN: Yale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrans CE. (2005). Definitions and conceptual models of quality of life. In, (Eds.) J Lipscomb, CC Gotay, C Synder. Outcomes Assessment in Cancer. New York NY: Cambridge University Press. (p. 14–30).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganz PA, Lee JJ, Siau J. (1991). Quality of life assessment. An independent prognostic variables for survival in lung cancer. Cancer. 67, 3131–3135.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P. (2000). Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Though. Lexington MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P. (2007). Representing actions and functional properties in conceptual spaces. In, (Eds.) T Ziemke, J Zlatev, RM Frank. Body, Language and Mind: Volume 1 Embodiment. Berlin Germany: Mouton de Gruyter. (p. 167–195).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill TM, Feinstein AR. (1994). A critical appraisal of the quality of quality of life measurements. JAMA. 272, 619–626.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Green RL. (1956). The Book of Nonsense. New York, NY: Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haase JE, Braden CJ. (1998). Guidelines for achieving clarity of concepts related to quality of life. In, (Eds) CR King, PS Hinds. Quality of life: From Nursing and Patient Perspectives. Theory, Research, Practice. Sudbury MA: Jones and Bartlett. (P. 54–73).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn U, Chater N. (1997). Concepts and similarity. In, (Eds.) K Lambert, D Shanks. Knowledge, Concepts and Categories. East Sussex United Kingdom: Psychological Press. (p. 43–93).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA. (1952). The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundation of Theoretical Psychology. Chicago Ill: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA. (1994). Hayek on Hayek: An Autobiographic Dialogue. (editors) Kresge S, Wenar L. Chicago Ill: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinemann AW, Fisher WP Jr, Gershon R. (2006). Improving health care quality with outcomes management. J Prosthet Orthot. 18, 46–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry F, Mc Vitte C. (2004). Is quality of life a healthy concept? Measuring and understanding life experiences of elderly people. Qual Health Res. 14, 961–975.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Henning H. (1916). Die qualitätenriehe des geschmacks. Z Psychol Physiol Sinnesortan. 74, 203–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horyn C. (2007). Après Rehab: A lovely sobriety. The New York Times. August 23, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt SM. (1997). The problem of quality of life. Qual Life Res. 6, 205–212.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Idler EL. (1999). Self-assessment of health: The next stage of studies. Res Aging. 21, 387–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Idler EL, Benyamini Y. (1997). Self-rated health and mortality: A review of twenty-seven community studies. J Health Soc Behav. 38; 21–37

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Idler E, Leventhal H, McLaughlin J, Leventhal E. (2004). In sickness but not in health; Self-ratings, identity and mortality. J Health Soc Behav. 454, 336–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illich I. (1977). Toward a History of Needs. New York NY: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philos Q. 32, 127–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce CRB. (1988). Quality of life: The state of the art in clinical assessment. In, (Eds.) SW Walker, RM Rosser. Quality of life Assessment and Application. Lancaster PA: MTP Press. (p. 169–179).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Krueger AB. (2006). Developments in the measurement of subjective well-being. J Econ Perspect. 20, 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan R, Anderson JP. (1990). The General Health Policy Model: An integrated approach. In, (Ed.) B Spilker. Quality of life Assessments in Clinical Trials. New York NY: Ravens.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan M, Berthelot J-M, Feeny D, McFarland BH, et al. (2007). The predictive validity of health-related quality of life measures; mortality in a longitudinal population-based study. Qual Life Res. 16. 1539–1546.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Koch C. (2004). Qualia. Cur Biol. 14, R496.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Krause N, Kay G. (1994). What do global self-rated health items measure? Med Care. 32, 930–942.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kupers R, Fumal A, Maertens de Moorhout A, et al. (2006). Transcranial magnetic stimulation of the visual cortex induces somatotopically organized qualia in blind subjects. Proc Nat’l Acad Sci. 103, 13256–13260.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Layard R. (2005). Happiness: Lessons from a New Science. New York, NY: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiss W. (1976). The Limits of Satisfaction: An Essay on the Problem of Needs and Commodities. Toronto CA: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas E. (1969/1961). Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. (Trans. A, Lingus) Pittsburgh PA: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis CI. (1929). Mind and the World Order. New York NY: C. Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Cambridge MA:Belknap Press/Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McHorney CA, Ware JE, Rogers W, et al. (1992). The validity and relative precision of MOS short-and long-form health status scales and Dartmouth COOP charts: results from the Medical Outcome Study. Med Care. 30, MS253-MS265.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • McKeon R. (1947). Introduction to Aristotle. New York NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T, Walde B. (2000). Commentary of Jakab’s “Ineffability of Qualia”. Conscious Cogn. 9, 352–362 doi:1186/1477-7525-3-64.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Michaels RK, Makary MA, Dahab Y, Frassica FJ, et al. (2007). Achieving the Quality Forum’s “Never Events:” prevention of wrong site, wrong procedure, and wrong patient operation. Ann Surg. 245, 526–532.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Michotte A. (1963). The Perception of Causality. New York NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morreim EH. (1986). Computing the quality of life. In, (Eds.)GJ Agich, CE Begley. The Price of Health. Dordrecht The Netherlands: Reidel. (p 45–69).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nord E, Arnesen T, Menzel P, Pinto J-L. 2001 Towards a more restricted use of the term “Quality of life”. News Letter Qual Life.26, 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nosofsky RM. (1986). Attention, similarity and the identification-categorization relationship. J Exp Psychology: Learn Mem Gen. 115, 39–57.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Nosofsky RM. (1992). Similarity scaling and cognitive process models. Annu Rev Psychol. 43, 25–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunn JA, Gregory LJ, Brammer M, Williams SCR, et al. (2002). Functional magnetic resonance imaging of synaesthesia activation of V4/V8 by spoken words. Nat Neurosci. 5, 371–375.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M, Sen A. (1993). The Quality of life: Studies in Developmental Economics. New York NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogden CK, Richards IA. (1946). The Meaning of Meaning. New York NY: Harcourt, Brace and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce JMS. (2007). Synaesthesia. Exp Neurol. 57, 120–124.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Pirsig RM. (1974). Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. New York NY: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pirsig RM. (1991). Lila: An Inquiry Into Mass Morals. New York NY: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priebe S, Kaiser W, Huxley PJ, Röder-Wanner, Rudolf H. (1998). Do different subjective evaluation criteria reflect distinct constructs? J Nerv Ment Dis. 188, 385–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapley M. (2003). Quality of life Research. Thousand Oaks CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read H. (1972). The meaning of art. London UK: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reber R, Schwarz N, Winkielman P. (2004). Process fluency and ­aesthetic pleasure: Is beauty in the perceived processing experience? Personal Soc Psychol Rev. 8, 364–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeves CA, Bednar DA. (1994). Defining quality: Alternatives and implications. Acad Manag Rev. 19, 419–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson M. (2008). Zen and Now: On the Trial of Robert Pirsig and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. New York NY: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser R, Kind P. (1978). A scale of valuations of states of illness: Is there a social consensus? Int J Epidemiol. 7, 347–358.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ruta DA, Garratt AM, Leng M, Russell IT, et al. (1994). A new approach to the measurement of quality of life: The Patient Generated Inventory (PGI). Med Care. 32, 1109–1126.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Santayana, G. (1955/1896). The sense of beauty. New York NY: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer KR. (2000). Emotions as episodes of subsystem synchronization driven by nonlinear appraisal processes. In, (Eds.) MD Lewis, I Granic. Emotions, Development, and Self-organization: Dynamic Systems Approaches to Emotional Development. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. (p. 70–99).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard RN. (1962a). The analysis of proximities: Multidimensional scaling with an unknown distance function: I. Psychom. 27, 125–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard RN. (1962b). The analysis of proximities: Multidimensional scaling with an unknown distance function: II. Psychom. 27, 219–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard RN. (1987). Towards a universal law of generalization. Sci. 237, 1317–1323.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sirgy MJ, Michalos AC, Ferriss AL, Easterline RA, et al. (2006). The Quality of life research movement: Past, present and future. Soc Indics Res. 76, 343–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan JA, Loprinzi CL, Kuross SA, et al. (1998). Randomized comparison of four tools measuring overall quality of life in patients with advanced cancer. J Clin Oncology. 16, 3662–3673.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer WO, Dobson AJ, Hall J, Chesterman E, et al. (1981). Measuring the quality of life of cancer patients. J Chronic Dis. 34,585–597.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Torrance GW. (1976). Health status index models: A unified mathematical view. Manag Sci. 22, 990–1001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrance GW, Furlong W, Feeny D, Boyle M. (1995). Multi-attribute preference functions: Health Utilities Index. PharmEcon. 7, 503–520.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Tye M. (1986). The subjective qualities of experience. Mind New Ser. 95,1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Osch SMC, Stiggelbout AM (2005). Understanding VAS valuations: Qualitative data on the cognitive process. Qual Life Res. 14, 2171–2175.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ware JE, Brook RH, Davis-Avery A, Williams KN, et al. (1980). Conceptualization and Measurement of Health for Adults in the Health Insurance Study: Vol. 1, Model of Health and Methodology. Santa Monica CA: Rand. Publication No R-1987/1 HEW.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis G, Reeve B, Barofsky I. (2005). The Use of Cognitive Interviewing Techniques in Quality of life and Patient-Reported Outcome Assessment. In, (Eds.) J Lipscomb, CC Gotay, C Synder. Outcomes Assessment in Cancer: Findings and Recommendations of the Cancer Outcomes Measurement Working Group. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L. (1961). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. New York NY: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfensberger W. (1994). Lets hang up “quality of life” as a hopeless term. In, (Ed.) D. Goode. Quality of life for Persons with Disabilities: International Perspectives and Issues. Cambridge, Brookline. (p. 285–321).

    Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organization. (1948). Constitution of the World Health Organization: Basic documents. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zullig KJ, Valois RF, Drane JW. (2005). Adolescent distinctions between quality of life and self-rated health in quality of life research. Health Qual Life Res. 3, 1–9, doi: 1186/1477-7525-3-64.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivan Barofsky .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Barofsky, I. (2012). The Difficulty of Assessing Quality or Quality-of-Life. In: Quality. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-9819-4_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-9819-4_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4419-9818-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4419-9819-4

  • eBook Packages: MedicineMedicine (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics