Skip to main content

Sustainable Development and Critical Theory

  • Chapter
Taking Complexity Seriously
  • 86 Accesses

Abstract

What is sustainable development? Why is it an issue? Ideally, what needs to be done ? and Practically, what can be done? are answered through the Critical theory of Paul Piccone and his colleagues at the journal, Telos, particularly Tim Luke who has made an extended critique of sustainable development.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Critical theory means many things, some of which stand in sharp contrast to the neo-Adornian brand articulated in Telos framework. This chapter has kept the journal’s capitalization of the term. Although having the same roots, the Telos version of Critical theory bears little resemblance to the much better known Habermassian variant.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The following three paragraphs are based on Piccone (1978, 48); Piccone (1987/88, 6-8); and Piccone (1991, 34-35).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Piccone (1991, 17).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Marcuse (1965) and Sinfield (1992). As for cycles of overregulation and underregulation, they occur this way: A government (agency, court, legislature) proceeds to adopt more and more regulations to manage what are seen as severe problems of concern. As the number of regulations increase, the regulatory process becomes more timeconsuming and the pace of implementing regulations slows down. The slower the implementation and the faster the growth of problems, the more problems appear unregulated. The more underregulation, the greater the pressure on government to micromanage problems by adopting even tougher regulations. But more numerous and stringent regulations slow even further the pace of implementation, and the cycle begins anew. For a sampling of the literature on micromanagement, see Mendeloff (1988, 1-17); Gregory (1989); and Wilson (1989, 241-244 and 366-368).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Luke (forthcoming, University of Minnesota Press). For an early discussion of these issues, see the interchange between Barry Commoner and members of the Telos group in the section on “The Totally Administered Society,” Telos 78 (Spring, 1978), pp. 169-184.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Luke (1995, 207).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid (213).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid (437).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid (271-272).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid (228-229). See also the discussion on “analytic tip” in Roe (1994b).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Luke (Chapter 10).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid (451).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Rubenstein (1993, 585-586).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Salwasser (588).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Levin (unnumbered page)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Meyer and Helfman (571).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Holling (554; highlights in the original).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Even if this system complexity were not real, from a Critical theory perspective New Class ecologists would have very likely invented the concept as a form of artificial negativity to justify their continued work. In this view, major US problems are complicated because they “arise,” not to be solved, but to keep the New Class busy.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Mangel et al (573).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Piccone (1987/88, 7-8).

    Google Scholar 

  21. See, for example, Mooney and Sala, Mangel et al, and Ehrlich and Daily.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See, for example, Meyer and Helfman (570). “Include human motivation by developing linkages with the social sciences, particularly economics, to develop a comprehensive transdisciplinary synthesis,” is how Costanza (580) puts what is a wonderful, albeit unintentional, illustration of New Class artificial negativity at work—as if a major problem with resource managerialism is the need to link human motivation to the social sciences!

    Google Scholar 

  23. Respectively, Mangel et al (574); Meyer and Helfman (569). There is one sense in which sustainable systems and organic communities are similar, i.e., some would describe each as “self-correcting,” though in fundamentally different ways For a few, the appeal of sustainable development is the promise that human systems can mimic ecosystems, in that they both can be self-correcting, i.e., self-sustaining. “Participants,” to one recent conference on ecosystem management, “focused on the need to develop solutions that enhanced the flexibility of the system itself to respond to natural fluctuations and’ self-correct’” (California Urban Water Agencies, “Ecosystem Management: The Bay-Delta Solution,” Final Report (July 1995), p. ES-2. Indeed, it is fairly easy to see in such comments an appeal to systems that need only a minimum of human interventions, New Class or otherwise (for more, see Chapter 4). The “corrections” put into place through organic communities and populism, of course, are nothing without those human interventions.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Lee (561).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Respectively, Mangel (573); Meyer and Helfman (569).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See, for example, Zedier (578); Costanza (580).

    Google Scholar 

  27. See Meyer and Helfman (570); Slobodkin (572).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Slobodkin (572).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Roe (1994b).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Robert Solow, the Nobel economist, captures this persecutory tone when, in his discussion of sustainable development, he complains that “there is something faintly phony about deep concern for the future combined with callousness about the state of the world today” (quoted in Levin, unnumbered page).

    Google Scholar 

  31. See, for example, Pitelka and Pitelka, and Rubenstein. It should go without saying that some ecologists see the “technocratic ideas” that motivate sustainable development (e.g., Lee, 560).

    Google Scholar 

  32. For example, Salwasser (588).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Mangel et. al., for example, equate ecosystems with “renewable resources” (573).

    Google Scholar 

  34. For more, see Roe (1995).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Global warming is discussed in Roe (1994b). 35 Piccone (1991); D’Amico and Piccone (1992).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See Piccone (1991, 38ff) on the importance of territory to organically constituted communities. For a criticism of Piccone’s notion of community, see Fortmann and Roe (1993). For a very Picconesque argument about the difference between community and management, but from a different perspective, see Post (1995, 3-15).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Roe, E. (1998). Sustainable Development and Critical Theory. In: Taking Complexity Seriously. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-5497-4_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-5497-4_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4613-7511-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4615-5497-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics