Skip to main content

Thinking Outside the Square of Opposition Box

  • Chapter
Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition

Part of the book series: Studies in Universal Logic ((SUL))

Abstract

The graphic meaning and formal implications of the canonical Aristotelian square of opposition are favorably compared with alternative ways of representing subsyllogistic logical relations among the four categorical AEIO propositions of syllogistic logic. The canonical arrangement of AEIO propositions in the square is justified by an exhaustive survey of graphically nonequivalent alternatives. The conspicuous omission in a modified expanded Aristotelian square of inversions involving complements of subject terms is critically considered. Two of the four inversions are shown to be logically equivalent to two of the AEIO propositions, and are consequently discounted as offering no potential significant revision of the canonical square. The remaining two inversions are logically distinct from any of the AEIO propositions, and the advantages of adding them to an expanded square are explored. It is shown that the two AEIO-distinct inversions are inferentially, and as contraries, subcontraries, subalterns or contradictories, logically isolated from the AEIO propositions. From this it seems reasonable to conclude that no inversion makes a contribution to the subsyllogistic logical relations represented in an expanded version of the square. The investigation leaves the traditional Aristotelian square unchanged, but affords a deeper appreciation of the canonical square’s optimal two-dimensional diagramming of subsyllogistic logical relations among the four fixed AEIO propositions, and of why inversions of the AEIO propositions are appropriately excluded from the square. The limits and disadvantages of subsyllogistic logic are made conspicuous in the use of contemporary classical logic to translate and verify in algebraic terms all potential square of opposition relations, as a formal basis for excluding inversions, where they are otherwise manifestly excluded without explanation from the canonical square.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Aristotle’s Prior Analytics and De Interpretatione in [1], [24], [25], [27], [4], [5], [18, 17–65], [19].

  2. 2.

    [2, 3, 10, 17, 21].

  3. 3.

    [8, 9, 26].

  4. 4.

    After Frege, Peano and Boole there is increasingly less interest in syllogistic logic, and so with the canonical Aristotelian square of opposition. See [16, especially 177–198, 404–427]. Boole [6, 7] in particular marks the turning point in logic, beginning with an expanded formulation of Aristotelian syllogistic logic, enhanced especially by William Hamilton to a four term logic, which Boole then converts to algebraic formulation at exactly the transitional midpoint between Aristotelian-Scholastic and contemporary symbolic logic.

  5. 5.

    [20, 105–106]. On 105, McLaughlin rightly asks: ‘Writers have also criticized the traditional process called ‘inversion,’ which licenses the inference from ‘All S is P’ to ‘Some non-S is not P’—in our terms, from s[p(N)] to −(−s[p(N)]) or −s[−p(M)]. Why must it be the case that if all S is P, some non-S is not P? After all, if it were the case that everything is P, then all things S and non-S alike would be P. But when ‘All S is P’ is taken to mean that a thing’s being S warrants the conclusion that it is P, and when the problem is addressed from the point of view of OC [McLaughlin’s theory of Ordinary Conditionals], the inference becomes entirely natural. Because s[p(N)] means only that the presence of s ensures the presence of p.’ McLaughlin’s final remark suggests that N plays no role in the meaning of s[p(N)], which would need to be explained. McLaughlin says that s[p(N)] means that the ‘presence’ of s ensures the ‘presence’ of p, which is patently a metaphysical relation of ontic dependence or supervenience. It is a metaphysical relation, if ‘presence’ means as it appears ‘existence’, anyway, surely not just presence to us at a particular time, rather than the expected logical or semantic relation by which an inversion at least of an AEIO proposition might first be explicated. McLaughlin’s interpretation supports an interesting and plausible interpretation by which, for example, the meaning of the A proposition, ‘All whales are mammals’, is directly bound to specific truth conditions by which the presence of whales ensures the presence of mammals, and, indeed, the presence of any whale ensures the presence of a mammal.

  6. 6.

    Lukasiewicz [12] does not even consider AEIO inversions in his second edition of Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. Among the few available sources for the topic is [11]; a valuable study in its own right that is not concerned with the particular questions that I have been investigating. Prior [22, 23] discusses negative terms in Boethius’s syllogistic logic, citing the latter’s Introductio ad Syllogismos Categoricos, but does not mention inversions by that name. See especially [23, Part II, Chapter II—Categorical Forms with Negative, Complex, and Quantified Terms, 126–156; including §1 Negative Terms in Boethius and de Morgan, 126–134].

  7. 7.

    [15, v].

  8. 8.

    [15, 147].

  9. 9.

    [15, 118].

  10. 10.

    [15, 119].

  11. 11.

    [15, 139]. Keynes refers to Jevons [13, 185–186].

  12. 12.

    [15, 144], [14, (vol. I) 142]. Keynes does not refer to a specific source prior to the publication of Johnson’s 1921 from which he might have derived the octagon of opposition.

  13. 13.

    Keynes is explicit about the logical equivalence or equipollence of the E′ (E(V)) and A and between I′ (I(V)) and O inversions with their canonical categorical propositional forms. Johnson [14, (vol. I), 140] defines the inversions equivalent, using a short horizontal bar above subject and predicate terms to indicate their internal ‘negations’ or complements. Having presented the equivalences, however, he appears to deny that there are any equivalences between the inversions and the standard AEIO propositions, when he concludes immediately thereafter on the same page, that the enumeration provides ‘a list of eight distinct [Johnson’s emphasis] (i.e. non-equipollent) [Johnson’s parenthetical clarification] general categoricals, as an extension of the usual four.’ This certainly seems false, at least from a more contemporary logical perspective, as well as being at odds with Keynes’ understanding.

References

  1. Aristotle: The Complete Works of Aristotle. J. Barnes (ed.). Princeton University Press, Princeton (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bird, O.: Syllogistic and Its Extensions. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Boehner, P.: Medieval Logic. Manchester University Press, Manchester (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Boethius, A.M.T.S.: Dialectica Aristotelis. Sebastian Gryphius, Lyons (1551)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Boethius, A.M.T.S.: Comentarii in librum Aristotelis (Peri Hermeneias [De Interpretatione]). Meiser, K.C. (ed.). B.G. Teubneri, Leipzig (1877)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Boole, G.: The Mathematical Analysis of Logic: Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning. George Bell, London (1847)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Boole, G.: An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which Are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Walton and Maberley, London (1854)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Carroll, L.: Symbolic Logic [1896]. Bartley, W.W. III (ed.). Clarkson N. Potter, New York (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Euler, L.: Elements of Algebra [1802]. Hewlett, J. (trans.). Springer, New York (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Howard, D.T.: Analytical Syllogistics: A Pragmatic Interpretation of the Aristotelian Logic. Northwestern University Press, Evanston (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Iwanus, B.: Remarks about syllogistic with negative terms. Stud. Log. 24, 131–137 (1969)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Lukasiewicz, J.: Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic, 2nd edn., enlarged. Clarendon, Oxford (1955)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Jevons, W.S.: Elementary Lessons in Logic: Deductive and Inductive with Copious Questions and Examples and a Vocabulary of Logical Terms, 7th edn. Macmillan, London (1879)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Johnson, W.E.: Logic, 3 vols. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1921–1924)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Keynes, J.N.: Studies and Exercises in Formal Logic: Including a Generalisation of Logical Processes in Their Application to Complex Inferences. 4th edn., re-written and enlarged. Macmillan, London (1906)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Kneale, W., Kneale, M.: The Development of Logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1962)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Lejewski, C.: Aristotle’s syllogistic and its extensions. Synthese 15, 125–154 (1963)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Marenbon, J.: Boethius. Oxford University Press, New York (2003). For notes: 17–65

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Martin, C.J.: The logical textbooks and their influence. In: Marenbon, J. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Boethius, pp. 56–84. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2009)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. McLaughlin, R.N.: On the Logic of Ordinary Conditionals. SUNY, Albany (1990)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Peterson, P.L.: Syllogistic Logic and the Grammar of Some English Quantifiers. Indiana University Press, Bloomington (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Prior, A.N.: The logic of negative terms in Boethius. Francisc. Stud. 13, 1–6 (1953)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Prior, A.N.: Formal Logic, 2nd edn. Clarendon, Oxford (1962)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Smith, R.: Logic. In: Barnes, J. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, pp. 27–65. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Thom, P.: The Logic of Essentialism: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic. Springer, Berlin (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Venn, J.: Symbolic Logic [1894]. 2nd edn. Franklin Philosophy Monographs, New York (1971)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Woods, J., Irvine, A.: Aristotle’s early logic. In: Gabbay, D., Woods, J. (eds.) Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 1: Greek, Indian and Arabic Logic, pp. 27–100. Elsevier (North Holland), Amsterdam (2004)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to an anonymous commentator for useful suggestions and criticisms in preparing the final version of this essay. Special thanks are due to my research assistant Sebastian Elliker at Universität Bern and Tina Marie Jacquette for digitalizing my hand-drawn diagrams.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dale Jacquette .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Basel

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jacquette, D. (2012). Thinking Outside the Square of Opposition Box. In: Béziau, JY., Jacquette, D. (eds) Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition. Studies in Universal Logic. Springer, Basel. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-0348-0379-3_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics