Skip to main content

Theory-Parts for Scientific Realists

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
EPSA11 Perspectives and Foundational Problems in Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings ((EPSP,volume 2))

  • 953 Accesses

Abstract

The “divide and conquer” approach to scientific realism requires a compelling criterion for specifying theory-parts worthy of realist commitment – components deemed very probably true. Articulating such a criterion has proved difficult, however. Long-term retention across theory-change provides a poor basis at best (judging by examples like the ether of light); the same can be said about such features as empirical success and current freedom from specific doubts. This paper argues for a seemingly better choice, drawn from scientific practice and focused on five overlapping strategies: hostile probing of a theory’s central tenets by its opponents, revision of auxiliary assumptions (mainly by supporters of the theory), external grounding of theoretical assumptions, efforts to identify adequacy conditions for successor theories, and explanations of a theory’s success after becoming superseded.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kitcher (1993), Leplin (1997), Psillos (1999), and Thagard (2000, 2007).

  2. 2.

    See, for example, Sulloway (1992) on relevant works by Sigmund Freud, Franz Alexander, Sigfried Bernfeld & Sergei Feitelberg, Heinz Lichtenstein, and Leon Saul.

  3. 3.

    Kepler (1620/1995), Davis (2003).

  4. 4.

    I am referring particularly to Worrall (1989) and Leplin (1997).

  5. 5.

    Whewell (1968) and Darwin (1859).

  6. 6.

    Typically, these parts correspond to applications of T grounded in models subjected to abstraction, domain-restriction, and coarse-graining (partial-models of T). See Cordero (2013).

  7. 7.

    In Whewell (1847, pp. 67–68) he says: “No example can be pointed out, in the whole history of science, so far as I am aware, in which this Consilience of Inductions has given testimony in favour of an hypothesis afterwards discovered to be false. … [W]hen the hypothesis, of itself and without adjustment for the purpose, gives us the rule and reason of a class of facts not contemplated in its construction, we have a criterion of reality, which has never yet been produced in favour of falsehood”.

References

  • Balashov, Y. (1994). Duhem, Quine, and the multiplicity of scientific tests. Philosophy of Science, 61, 608–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1957). Causality and chance in modern physics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (2004). Experimental success and the revelation of reality. In M. Carrier et~al. (Eds.), Knowledge and the world (pp. 137–161). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2003). The structuralist conception of objects. Philosophy of Science, 70, 867–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2003). Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric. Philosophy of Science, 70, 902–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordero, A. (2011a). Rejected posits, realism, and the history of science. In The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings (Vol. 1, pp. 23–32). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordero, A. (2011b). Scientific realism and the divide et impera strategy: The ether saga revisited. Philosophy of Science, 78, 1120–1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordero, A. (2013). Conversations across Meaning Variance. Science & Education 22, 1305–1313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859) On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, A. E. L. (2003). Conversations across Meaning Variance. Science & Education 22, 1305–1313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kepler, J. (1620/1995). Epitome of Copernican astronomy, Book IV (trans: Charles G. Wallis). Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. Philosophical Review, 93, 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). A confutation of convergent realism. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp.218–249). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulloway, F. (1992). Freud, biologist of the mind: Beyond the psychoanalytic legend. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2007). Coherence, truth, and the development of scientific knowledge. Philosophy of Science, 74, 28–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1847). The philosophy of the inductive sciences (Section III – Tests of hypothesis, Vol. II). London: John W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1858/1968). Chapter III, Induction and scientific method. In E. Robert (Ed.), William Whewell’s theory of scientific method (pp. 103–264). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Fresnel, Poisson and the white spot: The role of successful prediction in the acceptance of scientific theories. In G. Gooding et~al. (Eds.), The uses of experiment (pp.135–157). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I wish to thank an anonymous referee for valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Cordero .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this paper

Cite this paper

Cordero, A. (2013). Theory-Parts for Scientific Realists. In: Karakostas, V., Dieks, D. (eds) EPSA11 Perspectives and Foundational Problems in Philosophy of Science. The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01306-0_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics