Skip to main content

On the Interpretation of Dependent Plural Anaphora in a Dependently-Typed Setting

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence (JSAI-isAI 2016)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 10247))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

Anaphora resolution is sensitive to dependency relations between objects. One example, which is well known in the plural anaphora literature, is the dependent interpretation of the pronoun it in the mini-discourse Every boy received a present. They each opened it. The standard account of the dependent interpretation records dependency relations using sets of assignment functions (van den Berg [4, 5], Nouwen [17], Brasoveanu [7]). This approach, however, requires substantial changes to the central notion of context and gives special treatment to dependent interpretations. In this paper we provide an alternative account from the perspective of dependent type theory (Martin-Löf [16]). We account for dependency relations in terms of dependent function types (\(\varPi \)-types), which are independently motivated objects within dependent type theory. We will adopt Dependent Type Semantics (Bekki [1], Bekki and Mineshima [2]) as a semantic framework and illustrate how dependent function types encode dependency relations and naturally provide a resource for dependent interpretations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An anaphor is subscripted by an index, while its antecedent is superscripted by the same index.

  2. 2.

    This example is attributed to Lauri Karttunen in Hintikka and Carlson [10].

  3. 3.

    There are important differences between Ranta’s [18] framework and that of DTS. First, while Ranta did not adopt the framework of compositional semantics, DTS provides a compositional derivation of the semantic representations involving anaphora. Another difference between Ranta’s and our analysis is that Ranta interprets common nouns as types, while DTS treats them as predicates. More discussion on these points can be found in Bekki and Mineshima [2].

  4. 4.

    Some readers may think that proof terms have something in common with discourse referents in Discourse Representation Theory (Kamp and Reyle [12], Kamp et al. [11]) in that both objects are introduced by sentences and referred to afterward to resolve anaphora. There are at least two crucial differences. Firstly, as Ranta [18] discussed, while discourse referents are limited to individuals without any inner structure, proof terms can have any type. Secondly, together with the anaphora resolution mechanism provided in DTS, proof terms can contribute to logical inference, which yields a new proof term serving as an antecedent.

  5. 5.

    In the case of every, we can provide its semantic representation in two ways: one possibility is to treat it simply as a \(\varPi \)-type as we have seen above; another possibility is to represent it in the same way as other generalized quantifiers such as most. Since these two formulas are mutually deducible, the account of generalized quantifiers presented here can be applied to the case of every as well.

  6. 6.

    As \(\varPi \)-types correspond to the \(\forall \)\(\exists \) reading (or distributive reading), the semantic representation of three provided by Tanaka [19] should correspond to the semantic representation of three...each. To obtain the semantic representation of three...each in a compositional way, we can integrate the existing analysis of plural objects into our framework (see Link [15] for the standard approach; for the treatment of plural objects in a dependently-typed setting, see Boldini [6] and Chatzikyriakidis and Luo [8]). A full discussion of this phenomenon is beyond the scope of this paper.

References

  1. Bekki, D.: Representing anaphora with dependent types. In: Asher, N., Soloviev, S. (eds.) LACL 2014. LNCS, vol. 8535, pp. 14–29. Springer, Heidelberg (2014). doi:10.1007/978-3-662-43742-1_2

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Bekki, D., Mineshima, K.: Context-passing and underspecification in dependent type semantics. In: Chatzikyriakidis, S., Luo, Z. (eds.) Modern Perspectives in Type Theoretical Semantics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 98, pp. 11–41. Springer, Heidelberg (2017). doi:10.1007/978-3-319-50422-3_2

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Bekki, D., Satoh, M.: Calculating projections via type checking. In: Cooper, R., Retoré, C. (eds.) ESSLLI Proceedings of TYTLES Workshop on Type Theory and Lexical Semantics, ESSLLI, Barcelona (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  4. van den Berg, M.: Dynamic generalized quantifiers. In: van der Does, J., van Eijck, J. (eds.) Quantifiers, Logic, and Language, pp. 63–94. CSLI publications, California (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  5. van den Berg, M.: Some aspects of the internal structure of discourse: the dynamics of nominal anaphora. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Boldini, P.: The reference of mass terms from a type theoretical point of view. In: Proceedings of Forth International Workshop on Computational Semantics (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Brasoveanu, A.: Donkey pluralities: plural information states versus non-atomic individuals. Linguist. Philos. 31(2), 129–209 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Chatzikyriakidis, S., Luo, Z.: An account of natural language coordination in type theory with coercive subtyping. In: Duchier, D., Parmentier, Y. (eds.) CSLP 2012. LNCS, vol. 8114, pp. 31–51. Springer, Heidelberg (2013). doi:10.1007/978-3-642-41578-4_3

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  9. Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Dynamic predicate logic. Linguist. Philos. 14(1), 39–100 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Hintikka, J., Carlson, L.: Conditionals, generic quantifiers, and other applications of subgames. In: Saarinen, E. (ed.) Game-Theoretical Semantics. Synthese Language Library, vol. 3, pp. 179–214. Springer, Heidelberg (1979). doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-4104-4_7

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  11. Kamp, H., van Genabith, J., Reyle, U.: Discourse representation theory. In: Gabbay, D.M., Guenthner, F. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 15, pp. 125–394. Springer, Heidelberg (2011). doi:10.1007/978-94-007-0485-5_3

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Kamp, H., Reyle, U.: From Discourse to Logic: Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic and Discourse Representation Theory. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 42. Springer, Heidelberg (1993)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Karttunen, L.: Discourse referents. In: McCawley, J.D. (ed.) Syntax and Semantics, vol. 7, pp. 363–386. Academic Press, Cambridge (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Krifka, M.: Parametrized sum individuals for plural anaphora. Linguist. Philos. 19(6), 555–598 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Link, G.: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice-Theoretical Approach. de Gruyter, Berlin (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Martin-Löf, P.: Intuitionistic type theory: notes by Giovanni Sambin of a series of lectures given in Padua, Bibliopolis (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Nouwen, R.: Plural pronominal anaphora in context: dynamic aspects of quantification. Ph.D. thesis, Utrecht Institute for Linguistics OTS (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ranta, A.: Type-Theoretical Grammar. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1994)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Tanaka, R.: A proof-theoretic approach to generalized quantifiers in dependent type semantics. In: de Haan, R. (ed.) Proceedings of the ESSLLI2014 Student Session, pp. 140–151 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Tanaka, R., Nakano, Y., Bekki, D.: Constructive generalized quantifiers revisited. In: Nakano, Y., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds.) JSAI-isAI 2013. LNCS, vol. 8417, pp. 115–124. Springer, Heidelberg (2014). doi:10.1007/978-3-319-10061-6_8

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper is a revised and expanded version of a paper presented at the Logic and Engineering of Natural Language Semantics 13 (LENLS13). We would like to thank Alastair Butler, Yusuke Kubota, Robert Levine, the audience of the workshop ‘New landscapes in theoretical computational linguistics,’ two anonymous reviewers, and the audience of LENLS13 for their valuable comments, suggestions, and discussions. We are also grateful to Robin Cooper for helpful discussions on an earlier version of this paper. The first author acknowledges the financial support from JSPS (Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Research Fellow; 15J11772).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ribeka Tanaka .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Tanaka, R., Mineshima, K., Bekki, D. (2017). On the Interpretation of Dependent Plural Anaphora in a Dependently-Typed Setting. In: Kurahashi, S., Ohta, Y., Arai, S., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10247. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61572-1_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61572-1_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-61571-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-61572-1

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics